Skip to main content
Full access
Commentary
Published Online: 1 September 2018

Is Euthanasia Psychiatric Treatment? The Struggle With Death on Request in the Netherlands

A 42-year-old married woman with three children was referred to our department for treatment of treatment-resistant depression. Pharmacotherapy, psychotherapy, and ECT were unsuccessful. We applied deep brain stimulation, which was partially effective and reduced depressive symptoms by 30%, but the patient still suffered. During our struggle to find optimal deep brain stimulation parameters in the course of treatment, the patient requested that her general physician provide euthanasia. Following guidelines in the Netherlands, our team was consulted, but we disapproved because her suffering was not prospectless and there still were treatment options with deep brain stimulation. Although we had treated her intensively for 2 years, our advice was disregarded. Eight weeks later we received the obituary of the patient.

Euthanasia Versus Physician-Assisted Death

Euthanasia means that the physician acts directly to end the patient's life, e.g., by giving a lethal injection. Physician-assisted death means providing medical assistance to a person who requests to end life, often by self-administration of a lethal dose that the physician has prescribed for that purpose.
Seven countries and states have legalized or permitted euthanasia and physician-assisted death under existing law (1). The Dutch Termination of Life on Request and Assisted Suicide Act came into force in 2002. Goals of the law include providing legal security for all involved, assuring prudent practice with regard to euthanasia and physician-assisted death by physicians, and providing an adequate framework for physicians to be accountable and for increased transparency and societal control. Criteria for granting euthanasia in the Netherlands include a voluntary and well-considered request, the presence of unbearable and prospectless suffering as assessed by a physician, and the absence of reasonable treatment options after consultation with an independent physician (2).
Euthanasia has been found legitimate by the Dutch society on the grounds of two fundamental principles: the principle of compassion (counteracting unbearable suffering) and the principle of autonomy (the right of self-determination). Four to five in 10 people in the Netherlands are in favor of allowing people with a psychiatric illness to end their life on request; six to eight in 10 people favor it being allowed for people with dementia; four to six in 10 favor it being allowed for healthy older people who consider their life completed; and four in 10 favor it being allowed for children younger than age 12 (3).
The Netherlands has a population of nearly 17 million and has 147,000 annual deaths. The total number of explicit requests for euthanasia in 2016 was 17,900, of which 34% were granted, with 4.1% of all deaths being the result of euthanasia (N=6,091). One percent of reported euthanasia cases in 2016 were patients with psychiatric disorders. In 2016, Dutch psychiatrists received an estimated 1,100 euthanasia requests, of which 60 were granted. An estimated 3.4% (N=128) of psychiatrists (N=3,700) have ever granted a request. A survey among psychiatrists showed an increase in the estimated number of requests from 320 in 1995 to 500 in 2008 and then to 1,100 in 2016 (3).
The euthanasia act has ignited fierce debates among Dutch psychiatrists. Arguments pro euthanasia contend that it would be unfair to exclude psychiatric patients if they fulfill the due care criteria, that psychiatric suffering might be worse than somatic suffering, that euthanasia offers a dignified medical alternative to patients who otherwise might complete suicide, and that considering a request for assistance in suicide is part of the responsibility of a psychiatrist.
Arguments contra euthanasia maintain that the criteria for psychiatric suffering are less objective than somatic suffering, that psychiatric disorders per se are not life threatening, that the distinction between disorder-related and suffering-related desire to die is hard to establish, that there is a serious risk that the psychiatrist’s granting of a request is contaminated by countertransference, that the extent to which a request from an acutely ill psychiatric patient can be voluntary and well considered is doubtful, and that there is a question of whether one should consider granting a request for assisted death when the quality of mental health care is not sufficient.
Apart from controversy about the primary question, whether euthanasia is an option for psychiatric patients, there are medical and ethical dilemmas related to the practical process of decision making and execution. How can we reconcile the daily practice of reducing suicidal ideas and behaviors in patients with respecting a death wish in single cases? How can we distinguish between symptoms and existential needs? How can we decide whether a psychiatrist is sufficiently autonomous to judge euthanasia? Does the fragile therapeutic relationship between psychiatrist and patient not bias judgment? How are differences in opinion between psychiatrist and patient resolved? Although psychiatrists are not legally obliged to approve or execute euthanasia, neither can they interfere once a request is granted by a third party, as illustrated in the aforementioned case.
Psychiatrists in the Netherlands as well as in Belgium increasingly experience these practical dilemmas as professional problems. The possibility of a physician-assisted death adds a problematic new aspect to psychiatric treatment. For patients, it can become a seemingly perfect solution that precludes difficult therapeutic work to resolve problems in their lives and in themselves. For psychiatrists, it can be seen as the ultimate patient demand that carries the weight of transference and countertransference with an unprecedented seriousness. The possibility that the patient at any time is free to seek assistance with death from another physician may induce a frustrating therapeutic atmosphere.
The powerlessness psychiatrists may feel when facing a euthanasia request may be comprehended as moral distress. Moral distress is the state experienced when moral choices and actions “of doing the right thing” are constrained by conflicts of interests or public expectations. It arises for psychiatrists in their efforts to fulfill two conflicting roles; they are held accountable simultaneously for the healing of mental suffering and the preservation of life. Paradoxically, although the number of requests has increased in the Netherlands, psychiatrists have become more reluctant toward euthanasia. In 1995, 53% of psychiatrists found it inconceivable to ever consider euthanasia; in 2015, 63% of psychiatrists rejected euthanasia (3).
Nevertheless, euthanasia is a pressing public issue in the Netherlands. There is widespread public support for the current regulation of ending life on request, and it is expected that requests by psychiatric patients in the Netherlands will increase. Three developments encourage this growing demand: societal developments, the role of psychiatry, and the euthanasia act. First, Western societies are increasingly dominated by a drive toward more autonomy for the individual and the supreme right of self-determination. Being in control has become the ultimate moral virtue of Western citizens. We desire full control not only of our life but of our death as well. People believe it is necessary to regulate birth and now death. Second, in past decades, psychiatry has gradually shifted its goals from treating symptoms of “patients” with diseases to augmenting quality of life of “clients” who are mentally stressed. With an emphasis on quality of life instead of treatment, reduction of suffering has become a priority and a responsibility of psychiatry. Psychiatry now maintains a balance between the border of treating disorders and providing patients a happy life. Finally, the possibility of euthanasia may lower many people’s threshold for ending their lives. The legalization of euthanasia not only appears to justify morally the intention to die, it also institutes suppliers of the services who encourage the demand for euthanasia.
Euthanasia motivated by psychiatric disorders has been legal in the Netherlands since 2002. To date, the number of granted requests is limited, but rising public awareness increases annually the number of requests. There still is controversy about the role of euthanasia in psychiatry and its practical implementations. The debate exceeds medical decision making and is primarily based on ethical and philosophical grounds. Eventually, the position of an individual psychiatrist toward euthanasia and caring for life depends on his or her metaphysical perspective on death. Is death solely the end of life, or is death the start of a meaningful life? Whatever stance one takes in the euthanasia debate, albeit good or bad, right or wrong, in the end, there is a terminal effect. Euthanasia for psychiatric disorders is an infinite debate with finite consequences.

References

1.
Steck N, Egger M, Maessen M, et al: Euthanasia and assisted suicide in selected European countries and US states: systematic literature review. Med Care 2013; 51:938–944
2.
Wet toetsing levensbeëindiging op verzoek en hulp bij zelfdoding (Act on termination of life on request and assisted suicide). 2001, http://wetten.overheid.nl/BWBR0012410/2014-02-15
3.
Derde evaluatie Wet toetsing levensbeëindiging op verzoek en hulp bij zelfdoding. The Hague, ZonMw, 2017, series of evaluation regulations, part 40. https://www.rijksoverheid.nl/documenten/rapporten/2017/05/23/derde-evaluatie-wet-toetsing-levensbeeindiging-op-verzoek-en-hulp-bij-zelfdoding

Information & Authors

Information

Published In

Go to American Journal of Psychiatry
Go to American Journal of Psychiatry
American Journal of Psychiatry
Pages: 822 - 823
PubMed: 30173544

History

Accepted: 21 June 2018
Published online: 1 September 2018
Published in print: September 01, 2018

Keywords

  1. Other Psychological Issues
  2. Administration
  3. Assisted Suicide
  4. Death

Authors

Affiliations

Damiaan Denys, M.D., Ph.D. [email protected]
Dr. Denys is from the Psychiatry Program, Academic Medical Center, Amsterdam University Medical Center, University of Amsterdam, and the Netherlands Institute for Neuroscience, Amsterdam, and is President of the Dutch Society of Psychiatrists.

Notes

Address correspondence to Dr. Denys ([email protected]).

Funding Information

The author reports no financial relationships with commercial interests.

Metrics & Citations

Metrics

Citations

Export Citations

If you have the appropriate software installed, you can download article citation data to the citation manager of your choice. Simply select your manager software from the list below and click Download.

For more information or tips please see 'Downloading to a citation manager' in the Help menu.

Format
Citation style
Style
Copy to clipboard

There are no citations for this item

View Options

View options

PDF/ePub

View PDF/ePub

Get Access

Login options

Already a subscriber? Access your subscription through your login credentials or your institution for full access to this article.

Personal login Institutional Login Open Athens login

Not a subscriber?

Subscribe Now / Learn More

PsychiatryOnline subscription options offer access to the DSM-5-TR® library, books, journals, CME, and patient resources. This all-in-one virtual library provides psychiatrists and mental health professionals with key resources for diagnosis, treatment, research, and professional development.

Need more help? PsychiatryOnline Customer Service may be reached by emailing [email protected] or by calling 800-368-5777 (in the U.S.) or 703-907-7322 (outside the U.S.).

Media

Figures

Other

Tables

Share

Share

Share article link

Share