Bipolar Disorder is not Manic-Depressive Illness
The first misconception to clear up is that bipolar disorder is not the same thing as manic-depressive illness. Many colleagues think about psychiatry as if nothing existed before Ronald Reagan was president of the United States. In other words, they have no awareness of psychiatric nosology, in any scientific detail, before the radical revision of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Third Edition (DSM-III) in 1980.
Some say that the DSM may have many faults, but it is a good first step into discussing psychiatric nosology. Not if the first step takes one off a cliff.
In the case of mood illness, one has to stop before the first step to examine the question of whether the basic bipolar/major depressive disorder nosology is valid in the first place. In other words, to be able to even begin to assess the validity of the bipolar spectrum concept, one has to first assess the validity of the bipolar disorder concept. Many use the presumed validity of the latter to question the validity of the former. The opposite may be the case.
The best introduction to the concept of a bipolar spectrum is to go a step back before the bipolar concept itself, back to the earlier concept of manic-depressive insanity (MDI), usually associated with psychotic features. Introduced by
Kraepelin (1921), and slightly rephrased as manic-depressive illness (to include the majority of subjects without psychotic features), the MDI concept was divided officially in 1980 in the DSM-III into bipolar disorder and major depressive disorder (MDD) (
Goodwin and Jamison, 2007). This division is in turn a variation on the original division made in the 1950s by Karl Leonhard of MDI into bipolar and unipolar recurrent psychoses (
Leonhard, 1957), which, if broadened to include non-psychotic mood presentations, was rephrased in the 1960s and 1970s by American researchers (headed at the Washington University of St Louis) as bipolar illness and unipolar depressive illness (
Woodruff et al., 1974). This American revision of Leonhard’s idea was the basis for the Research Diagnostic Criteria (RDC) of the 1970s (
Spitzer et al., 1978), which was transformed into the DSM-III (
American Psychiatric Association, 1980). In that last transition, from the RDC to DSM-III, the American Psychiatric Association became involved, and decisions were no longer primarily based on research considerations, but on the political preferences of the profession (
Shorter, 2009). Since most American psychiatrists were psychoanalytic, they tended to use the DSM-II diagnosis of ‘neurotic depression’ frequently. Yet that term was excluded from the Washington University concept; unipolar depression consisted of severe recurrent depressive episodes. Neurotic depression was not severe (it was mild to moderate), not recurrent (it was chronic), not just depressive (anxious symptoms were prominent), and not episodic (it was constant) (
Roth and Kerr, 1994). Yet to pass DSM-III, the RDC criteria were altered to include all those features – being non-recurrent, chronic, and anxious – as also part of the unipolar depressive syndrome (
Shorter, 2009); this hybrid condition was renamed ‘major depressive disorder’. The word ‘disorder’ was tagged onto every DSM-III diagnosis to avoid making any etiological judgments (
Ghaemi, 2012); thus, the term ‘illness’, which implied a medical disease, was dropped, producing bipolar ‘disorder’ and MDD.
One can see, after all these distortions, that the bipolar disorder concept is
very different from manic-depressive illness. Also, one sees that MDD was broadened to include many types of depressive symptom presentations that were not seen as part of the disease of recurrent depression. In the classic studies on unipolar depression that led to DSM-III, the diagnosis was made only if there were three or more depressive episodes (
Perris, 1966): recurrence was seen as essential to the disease of unipolar depression, which was an ‘endogenous’ (
Leonhard, 1957) (i.e. biologically based) disease (even limited by Leonhard only to those with concurrent psychotic features).
In sum, the broad MDI concept as a medical disease was replaced by a rump concept of bipolar ‘disorder’, and a large concept of depressive symptom-complexes (MDD).
The very narrow bipolar disorder concept differs from the old MDI concept considerably. Not only is it much narrower, but its core feature is different. For bipolar disorder, the condition is defined by polarity: presence or absence of a manic episode (
Leonhard, 1957). For MDI, the condition is defined by episodicity: recurrent mood episodes define the illness, irrespective of polarity (
Kraepelin, 1921). Ten depressive episodes mean MDI. Ten manic episodes mean MDI. The fact that the episodes are depressive or manic is irrelevant. The number ‘10’ is relevant: recurrence defines the illness (
Goodwin and Jamison, 2007).
MDI means recurrent manic or depressive episodes. Bipolar disorder means recurrent manic and depressive episodes. These are quite different concepts.
Put otherwise, MDI is basically bipolar disorder plus much of what we call MDD. MDI is much broader than bipolar disorder.
Often it is said that DSM-III was neo-Kraepelinian (
Klerman, 1986). It was not: for mood illnesses, it was, and is,
neo-Leonhardian (
Ghaemi, 2013). By accepting the bipolar concept, DSM-III turned away from Kraepelin and toward Leonhard, and this process has now been taken for granted with DSM-IV and now DSM-5. Psychiatry has moved away from the Kraepelinian MDI concept to such an extent that many assume that the bipolar/MDD dichotomy is obviously true.
The bipolar spectrum concept is a way of trying to go back to the Kraepelinian MDI concept, or at least to reopen the scientific discussion such that we can revisit whether it was correct to make the decision in 1980 to divide MDI into a small bipolar and large MDD concept.
After DSM-III
For about two decades, the neo-Leonhardian consensus of DSM-III held. The only objections came from a few experienced clinical researchers: in the US, Hagop Akiskal (
Akiskal, 1983), and in Europe, Athanasios Koukopoulos (
Kukopulos et al., 1980). Akiskal began studies in the 1970s in the first specialized mood clinic in the US, and he identified many patients who seemed to fall in between the bipolar and unipolar categories of the Washington University school (
Akiskal, 1983). He thus proposed maintaining the bipolar/unipolar distinction, but broadening the bipolar category to include a ‘bipolar spectrum’ (
Akiskal, 1983). In this spectrum, he included atypical depressive presentations and mood temperaments. In Rome, Koukopoulos found that he could not confirm some of the claims made in favor of the unipolar/ bipolar dichotomy. In particular, he cast doubt on the treatment response criterion: many unipolar patients did not respond to antidepressants; they seemed to have other features of bipolarity, such as a highly recurrent course and early age of onset (
Kukopulos et al., 1980). Even the symptom distinction was debatable: Koukopoulos found that many depressed patients had manic symptoms, and many manic patients had depressive symptoms. In other words, mixed states were much more frequent than pure mania or pure depression (
Koukopoulos and Tundo, 1992), and thus the attempt to distinguish the two was difficult, and perhaps unnecessary. Both Akiskal and Koukopoulos returned to Kraepelin’s work and found confirmation of their findings in the observations of Kraepelin.
An important third critic was Frederick Goodwin, director of the National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH) in the US in the late 1980s and early 1990s when he published his classic textbook
Manic-Depressive Illness (
Goodwin and Jamison, 2007). Goodwin, with his coauthor Kay Jamison, reviewed the scientific literature, and found evidence contradicting the 1960s and 1970s literature that had led to the DSM-III neo-Leonhardian dichotomy. The genetic literature could be interpreted as supporting Kraepelin
or Leonhard: mania did seem to run in families, but there was as much depression (or more) in families of manic probands as in families of depressive probands (
Gershon et al., 1982). In other words, depression did not run in families separate from mania. Further, Goodwin noted that lithium was effective in recurrent depression, not just bipolar disorder (
Prien et al., 1974). As biological research grew in the 1990s and 2000s, it also became clear that neurotransmitter theories about catecholamines had been very simplistic in the 1970s (
Hyman and Nestler, 1996). Second messengers and long-term neuroplastic changes in the brain were seen in mood illnesses (
Manji, 1992), and there were often similarities between unipolar and bipolar disorder definitions in those biological mechanisms (
Manji et al., 2000).
In the 1990s and 2000s, the new class of atypical neuroleptics was developed, which showed clear efficacy in acute mania, but also, in many cases, efficacy for depressive episodes, not limited to bipolar disorder but even in MDD with some agents (
Nelson and Papakostas, 2009). Some anticonvulsants, such as lamotrigine, were much more effective in preventing depression rather than mania (
Goodwin et al., 2004), and the presumed strong efficacy of antidepressants in MDD was thrown into doubt with the discovery of a large number of negative unpublished studies (
Turner et al., 2008). In sum, the simplistic treatment response distinction between antidepressants for MDD and mood stabilizers/neuroleptics for bipolar disorder was greatly weakened.
Mood Lability is not Diagnostic of Bipolar Illness
A second common misconception of the bipolar spectrum concept is that its core feature is mood lability. Some argue that since mood lability is a diagnostic criterion for borderline personality, this approach leads to a ‘bipolarization’ of personality disorders (
Kuiper et al., 2012). In fact, this concern is based on not appreciating a scientific approach to nosology. All of DSM suffers from this unscientific bent. Suppose one wants to define a diagnosis by certain symptoms; which symptoms should one pick? The most common? The most different from other conditions? If you wish to describe pneumonia clinically, without any biological features, which symptoms would you pick? Fever? Or cough with productive sputum? Fever is a common and severe symptom of pneumonia, but it is nonspecific. Cough with productive sputum is less common, and less bothersome or
dysfunctional, but it reflects the underlying disease process. Here is a key difference between the non-Kraepelinian nosology of post-DSM-III psychiatry, and Kraepelin’s insight. Kraepelin directly rejected basing a nosology on symptoms. He wanted to base it on whatever clinical features reflected the underlying disease process (if a disease is present; an important point to be discussed later) (
Kraepelin, 1907). DSM uses the term ‘disorder’ as an agnostic, atheoretical appellation for all psychiatric constructs, and, to the extent this vague concept is defined, it is meant to reflect ‘harmful dysfunction’ (
Wakefield, 1992,
2007). Fever is quite a harmful dysfunction in pneumonia, but it doesn’t help us pick out that condition from others, nor does it help to get any progress in understanding its cause or cure.
Mood lability, along with anxiety, is the fever of psychiatry. It happens with many conditions, but it does not necessarily reflect underlying disease processes when present. Kraepelin felt that course of illness reflected the underlying disease process of manic-depressive insanity, and so he thought that other symptom presentations – such as depression versus mania, such as mood lability versus not – were not diagnostically important (
Kraepelin, 1921). Contrary to the linguistic assumption behind the title ‘mood’ disorders, ‘mood’ may not be central either to the diagnosis or pathophysiology of ‘mood disorders’. Rather, there is strong evidence that psychomotor activation is far more central to manic-depressive illness (
Cassano et al., 2012), not mood per se, and this can include rapid thinking, feeling and movement, which sometimes can be related to impulsivity, but often is not. In contrast, as we will see below, the core clinical features that represent the etiology and pathogenesis of borderline personality may also have nothing to do with mood lability, but rather dissociation.
Personality ‘Disorders’
When operationalized as above, our approach was limited to the Kraepelinian and Leonhardian concepts, in both of which the presumption was that patients experienced severe depressive episodes. Thus, the bipolar spectrum illness definition we gave presumed that patients had severe recurrent depressive episodes. In our view, this inclusion criterion automatically distinguished the bipolar spectrum illness definition from borderline personality. But, as some colleagues have noted (
Kuiper et al., 2012), the relationship between bipolar spectrum definitions and borderline personality is important and needs to be clarified.
In our minds, this clarification must include a more scientific understanding of what we mean by not only using the bipolar spectrum terminology, but also what we mean by the term ‘borderline’, and, more broadly, by the concept of ‘personality disorders’.
We use all these quotation marks because we are not certain that there is any scientific validity to the concept of personality disorders in general, much less borderline personality. Or, if there is such validity, it is of a quite different nature than the scientific validity of manic-depressive illness.
The first step, in our view, is to recognize that bipolar illness and borderline personality are
ontologically different. They are different types of things. Their similarities are superficial, their differences profound. The perception of similarity comes from using the term bipolar ‘disorder’ versus borderline personality ‘disorder’. The disorder term produces a linguistic equality which is not scientifically present. By using the term ‘disorder’, proponents of DSM categories have equalized all diagnoses (
Ghaemi, 2012). This is a major conceptual error, an ontological mistake, which means a mistake in understanding the basic nature of different things. Red skies differ from red apples; they are very different things; they are similar only superficially by being red in color. Similarly, manic-depressive illness is a disease of the body and brain, with many well-known biological abnormalities that are well replicated; it has been defined more or less as it is at least for a century or more; its definition is squarely in the medical model, requiring no beliefs beyond the acceptance of standard medical concepts such as signs, symptoms, syndromes, course, genetics, and biology. Borderline personality, in contrast, is, in our view, our culture’s interpretation of what used to be called ‘hysteria’. It is a Freudian interpretation of dissociative symptoms that happen in persons who experience trauma, usually sexual, early in life, in such a way that their personality development is derailed (
Gunderson, 1984). It requires the ideological commitment to a host of psychoanalytic speculations, such as transference, countertransference, projection, denial, and so on (
Gunderson, 1984). Its biology is poorly understood, and it is much less genetic than manic-depressive illness (
Bienvenu et al., 2011;
Kendler and Prescott, 2006). The concept, as now used, was invented relatively recently, about 40 years ago (
Kernberg, 1967,
1968).
These two clinical constructs are entirely different in their histories and key characteristics. All they share in common is mood lability and impulsivity. Many other psychiatric pictures include impulsivity (gambling addiction, substance abuse) or mood lability (frontal lobe syndrome, agitation of multiple causes). These superficial symptoms are like the redness of skies versus apples. They are not core features of these conditions, which differ so markedly in other ways.
It is well to give up the term ‘disorder’ and remind ourselves that superficial similarities are few, and major differences are many, when examining these conditions. Kraepelin distinguished between ‘disease-processes’ (
Krankheitsprozessen), such as MDI, and ‘clinical pictures’ (
Zustandsbilden) (
Beumont, 1992;
Decker, 2004) such as the whole range of anxious, mood, and dissociative symptom presentations that are seen in hysteria. The bipolar spectrum is a disease-process; borderline personality is a clinical picture, but not a disease. They differ in kind, although they have superficial symptom similarities. Neither is part of the other, nor should be confused with the other (
Bassett et al., 2012).
Red skies are not red apples.
Differentiating the Bipolar Spectrum Versus Borderline Personality
As noted previously, a major error leading to concerns about confusing the bipolar spectrum with borderline personality has to do with overemphasis on mood lability, which is not central to bipolar illness. Psychomotor activation is the key feature of bipolar illness that probably best reflects the disease process, along with the recurrent course. Similarly, mood lability can be seen as a superficial nonspecific symptom of borderline personality. Assuming borderline personality is a scientifically valid clinical construct, what clinical features represent its underlying pathogenic process?
To answer this question, it may be useful to ask a historical question beforehand: What did we used to call these patients before we began to call them borderline in the late 1960s (
Kernberg, 1967,
1968)? Pseudoneurotic schizophrenia immediately preceded the borderline term: these were patients who were usually neurotic, but then became psychotic when psychoanalyzed (
Hoch and Cattell, 1959;
Hoch and Polatin, 1949). They were on the
border (hence the later borderline term) between neurosis and psychosis, in the psychoanalytic metaphysics. Before pseudoneurotic schizophrenia, they tended to be called hysteria (
Micale, 1995), especially when their psychological symptoms were mixed with physical problems (such as paralysis) (
Shorter, 2006). Some were labeled as neurasthenia in the late 19th century. What did all these conditions have in common? At least in the Freudian tradition, from which the borderline concept derives, the etiology of these conditions was seen as the emotional effects of sexual trauma (real or imagined) (
Micale, 1995). The symptom presentations that were characteristic (as opposed to nonspecific; i.e. mood lability and anxiety) were generally seen as dissociative, with flashbacks, nightmares, and emotional numbing (
Micale, 1995;
van der Hart and Dorahy, 2006). Dissociative symptoms are common in borderline personality and rare in manic-depressive illness (
Benazzi, 2006;
Gunderson, 1984) Further, sexual trauma occurs in 50–70% of persons with borderline personality (
Fossati et al., 1999;
Soloff et al., 1994;
Wiederman et al., 1998;
Zanarini, 2000) versus 10–20% of the general population (
Briere and Elliott, 2003;
Molnar et al., 2001) and 20–30% of bipolar samples (
Conus et al., 2010;
Maniglio, 2013). Self-cutting and parasuicidal behavior happens consistently in 60–70% of persons with borderline personality (
Joyce et al., 2010) and as little as 0.9% of persons with bipolar illness (in over 5000 subjects examined in the National Comorbidity Survey) (
Nock and Kessler, 2006). Higher rates are found in clinical samples of bipolar illness (
Haw et al., 2001), and some report even higher rates in clinical bipolar samples than in borderline personality (
Joyce et al., 2010). Yet those conflicting reports are not replicated by other investigators (
Large et al., 2010), and do not outweigh data from the general population (
Nock and Kessler, 2006), which are more valid for the illness as a whole. They also do not outweigh the best quality evidence, available prospective studies, which indicate a clear relationship between sexual abuse, not bipolar illness, and parasuicidal behavior (
Fliege et al., 2009).
In sum, sexual abuse and parasuicidal behavior are many times more common in borderline personality than bipolar illness. If we take the historical and scientific literature seriously on mood temperaments, as we should, it seems scientifically indefensible to diagnose borderline personality in persons with family histories of bipolar illness, who meet diagnostic definitions of hyperthymia or cyclothymia, and who have no sexual abuse or self-cutting behavior. Yet, by slavishly following DSM criteria for borderline personality, such persons are commonly misdiagnosed as having that condition based on diagnostically non-specific features of mood instability, interpersonal conflicts, rejection sensitivity, sexual impulsivity, and anger. This kind of extremely broad definition of borderline personality, in contrast to the bipolar spectrum concepts described above, would appear to deserve the criticism of being vague and overinclusive. The epithet of bipolar ‘imperialism’, somewhat inappropriately made by some Western psychiatrists (
Paris, 2004), could more correctly be changed to
borderline imperialism: the clinical policy whereby any angry impulsive patient receives that label, often applied in a way that patients experience as pejorative (
Nehls, 1999), while all the other many causes for anger and impulsivity, including bipolar illness, are ignored or dismissed.
Biopsychosocial Errors
A common mistaken claim is that there are biological aspects to borderline personality, and thus it is not a mainly psychosocial condition. Further, it can be claimed that there are important psychosocial contributions to the development of bipolar illness, and thus it is not mainly a biological condition. These claims ignore the distinction between etiology and pathogenesis. Bipolar illness is almost completely genetic in its etiology, with over 80% genetic heritability based on twin studies; psychosocial factors hardly contribute at all to its etiology, based on the best summary of many genetic studies (
Bienvenu et al., 2011). It is false to claim that heritability is similar between bipolar illness and borderline personality: personality traits are only half as genetic as bipolar illness, not exceeding 50% when summarizing multiple studies (
Bienvenu et al., 2011). If the genetic predisposition to borderline personality is limited, as noted, the psychosocial contribution has been proven to be major. Thus, the two conditions are quite distinct in etiology.
The overlap claimed for biological and psychosocial factors for both conditions applies to pathogenesis, not etiology. Psychosocial factors can affect the course of bipolar illness (
Miklowitz, 2010), and the triggering of episodes (
Goodwin and Jamison, 2007), but not the inherent underlying etiological susceptibility to the illness itself (
Bienvenu etal.,2011).
Similarly, brain neurochemistry is affected by life experiences (
Kandel, 1999), thus sexual traumatic experience will have neurobiological effects. This can influence the course of borderline personality, but the presence of such neurobiological abnormality does not indicate a biological etiology for the condition. It is a consequence, not a cause.
Thus, studies which find similarities in neurobiology between bipolar illness and borderline personality (
Coulston et al., 2012) do not provide nosological evidence that the two conditions are the same, or that they overlap, unless such biological data can be shown to be etiologic, which is not the case.
The above misconceptions often reflect a strong attachment to the assumptions of the biopsychosocial model, which as we have shown elsewhere (
Ghaemi, 2009), is simply eclecticism, the combining of all perspectives for all conditions, producing the type of vague nosology that allows for the easy conflation of bipolar illness and borderline personality.
The Failed DSM Approach to Restricting Diagnostic Thresholds: Spectrum-Phobia
Much of the concern about spectra has to do with fear of overdiagnosis, or the false-positives problem. DSM leadership have responded to this fear by trying to keep the diagnostic thresholds for ‘disorders’ as high as possible (
Wakefield and First, 2012) – hence the antagonism to bipolar spectra, or to prodromal psychosis concepts (
Frances, 2009).
This solution has failed for 30 years, and it can be proven statistically to be highly likely to fail for another 30 years (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). True- or false-positives are reflected statistically as positive predictive values. To have low overdiagnosis, or low false-positives, means to have a high positive predictive value (PPV). PPV is dependent on the sensitivity and specificity of diagnostic criteria; the DSM approach is to make diagnostic criteria harder to meet so as to have high specificity. If spectra are allowed, the concern is that specificity would go down, and with it PPV. But PPV is much more dependent on the baseline prevalence of a condition than the specificity of a diagnostic test (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). All psychiatric conditions are low prevalence, in the statistical sense. Even conceived very broadly, bipolar spectrum illness definitions do not exceed 10% of the population (similar to the current broad MDD rates) (
Angst, 1998,
2007;
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). Even if extended by temperaments to 20% of the population, such rates are still low prevalence from the statistical PPV perspective. We have published simulations based on baseline prevalence rates near 10% for bipolar illness in unselected clinical populations, and we have shown that with that kind of low prevalence, one is guaranteed PPV rates of about 50% (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). That is, about half of all patients are falsely diagnosed as positive, producing the claim that bipolar illness is an overdiagnosed state (
Zimmerman et al., 2008). But the same ‘overdiagnosis’ would have happened with any psychiatric illness because of the impact of low prevalence on PPV, as shown in major epidemiological studies (
Smith and Ghaemi, 2010). In other words, this problem is not unique to bipolar illness; it is a problem with all psychiatric conditions. One would need specificities of above 95% to begin to get PPV rates around 70% (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012), and that kind of high specificity is very uncommon in psychiatric studies, including the best-designed DSM field trials (
Clarke et al., 2013;
Freedman et al., 2013;
Narrow et al., 2013;
Regier et al., 2013). Usual specificities are in the 70–80% range, even with our current DSM criteria, which refuse to recognize spectra for bipolar illness (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). Above 90% specificity is difficult to achieve with echocardiograms (
Ryan et al., 1993), much less clinical psychiatric interviews.
The solution should be obvious: to increase baseline prevalence. If baseline prevalence for bipolar illness was raised to 50%, then PPV would rise to 90%, assuming the same realistic specificities as currently obtained in psychiatric practice (in the 70–80% range) (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). How can we increase baseline prevalence rates? We could do so by examining non-symptom features that increase the prior probability of the condition, even before looking at specific manic or dissociative symptoms. This approach greatly increases true-positive diagnoses, and decreases false-positives (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). In bipolar illness, those diagnostic accuracy-enhancing features include a family history of bipolar illness and a severe episodic course with duration of episodes being weeks to months (
Phelps and Ghaemi, 2012). As noted, in borderline personality, those diagnostic accuracy-enhancing features include childhood sexual abuse and repeated non-suicidal self-injury (
Gunderson, 1984). These features are multiple times more frequent in borderline personality than in bipolar illness (
Nock and Kessler, 2006;
Zanarini, 2000).