Video Surveillance in Shared Spaces for Security Purposes
Psychiatric institutions primarily installed video surveillance to increase security for patients and staff (
1,
2,
5,
6,
8). Violence in psychiatric institutions is a serious concern for all persons involved, whether directed at staff by patients, among patients, or from staff toward patients (
12). For this reason, video surveillance is often intended to prevent, recognize, or document violent incidents, sexual assaults, theft, and other unwanted behavior (
5–
7). The benefit being sought, increased security, often has been thought to outweigh the loss of privacy involved (
5). However, the aspects of security that video monitoring was expected to improve (e.g., prevention of violence or self-harm and more rapid intervention by staff) has varied across studies and has often remained undefined (
1,
7,
8). In this article, security is understood as protection from intentional harms, in contrast to safety, which refers to prevention of accidental harms.
Empirical data have shown that video surveillance helps to create a sense of security among many patients and staff. A majority feels more secure in the presence of video surveillance (
1,
4,
5), with one study finding that 82.6% of patients believed that video surveillance increases the security and safety of patients and visitors on the ward (
1). However, no evidence was found that video surveillance—apart from an increased sense of security—increases objective security. Several smaller studies found no association between the occurrence of violent incidents and the presence of video surveillance on psychiatric wards (
2,
4,
6). Larger studies of video surveillance in other types of public areas also found no correlation between violent crime and the presence of cameras (
13).
An example of studies that failed to provide evidence of an impact of video monitoring on violence rates comes from Vartiainen and Hakola (
2), who examined the impact of renovations and the addition of video surveillance to a forensic ward. They found a drop in violent incidents from 70 in the year before the renovations to 57 (−18%) the next year. However, renovating the ward changed many variables at once, including reducing the number of beds from 50 to 39 (−22%). The authors suggested that the video monitoring may have had an impact on the number of violent incidents. However, this conclusion is questionable, considering the concomitant reduction in beds. If anything, it appears that the count of violent incidents per bed increased, although this was not reported in the study.
Paradoxically, use of video surveillance can have negative effects on security. Overreliance on video surveillance systems for security was one of the main criticisms from an investigation of a mental health ward in the United Kingdom after the death of a staff member as a result of assault by a patient (
14). Judging by the available evidence, the subjective increase in security does not translate into actual decrements in the frequency of violence and by itself cannot justify the use of video cameras in psychiatric institutions.
Possible Adverse Effects of Video Surveillance
Concerns have been expressed that the presence of video cameras might have an adverse effect on patients’ well-being (
1–
5,
8,
26). A study among 213 inpatients on a video-monitored secure ward found that 13 patients (6%) who experienced video surveillance in communal spaces felt that their symptoms of fear, distrust, or delusion were worsened (
1). In a study by Warr and colleagues (
4), patients also raised concerns that video cameras might increase paranoid thoughts. These data suggest that a certain percentage of patients might indeed be significantly negatively affected by video surveillance, but confirmation in other samples is needed. Although only a small percentage of patients are affected, these negative effects occur in the context of a lack of demonstrable evidence for benefits of video surveillance in public ward areas.
In addition, some experts have voiced concerns that the use of video cameras might directly contribute to an atmosphere of detachment, control, and fear, which could promote occurrence of the very events that surveillance is supposed to reduce (
6,
12). Because of a lack of empirical evidence, this can currently neither be confirmed nor refuted. It should be noted that undertaking to monitor public or private spaces on a ward may create a legal duty for staff to do so diligently, with possible civil liability or disciplinary sanctions imposed for lapses.
Consent
Whether patients need to consent to video monitoring is under debate. Stolovy and colleagues (
5) argued that a ward is a public space, and thus patient consent is not needed, but patients simply should be informed of the presence of cameras. Other authors have described similar approaches, in which patients were not asked for their consent but were informed of the presence of cameras (
6). In the German state of Nordrhein-Westfalen, policy makers went even further, arguing that a patient bedroom is also a public space, because staff members are allowed to enter without the patient’s permission (
1). This caused a heated public debate, which prompted the government of Nordrhein-Westfalen to prohibit video monitoring in psychiatric units altogether (
29).
However, control over decisions about video monitoring seems to be meaningful to many patients. Opinions on video monitoring on the ward and in bedrooms vary widely, with some patients finding it reassuring while others perceive it as an intrusion (
1,
4). It is likely that similar diversity exists for preferences regarding video surveillance during coercive measures, such as seclusion (
3), although this has not been studied.
The issue of consent is complicated by the fact that many patients who need to be monitored, potentially via video camera, are admitted involuntarily. Such patients may be antagonistic toward staff and not inclined to consent to video monitoring, even if it were likely to benefit them. One study, however, showed that patients who had been involuntarily admitted acknowledged the potential usefulness of video monitoring significantly more often than patients who had admitted themselves (69.6% versus 46.1%) (
1). In the same vein, voluntarily admitted patients more often expressed a perception of dehumanization from undergoing video monitoring in seclusion and restraint rooms. The reason for this was not evident from the data, but the authors suggested that it might stem from a sense of being wrongfully criminalized. This underlines the need to communicate with and explain the benefits of video monitoring to patients so that a suitable monitoring solution can be found, even for those admitted involuntarily. Because of the lack of evidence for objective benefits of video monitoring beyond patient preference, there currently are no data that support subjecting involuntarily admitted patients to video monitoring against their will.
So far, no significant differences have been found in overall attitudes on video monitoring in different patient populations (
1). However, patients with schizophrenia may have a more nuanced view than other patient groups, with twice as many (14.8%) objecting to video monitoring in seclusion and restraint rooms, whereas only 7.4% objected to surveillance in shared spaces (
1). This finding suggests that video monitoring is a complex subject that needs to be considered in a differentiated manner on a case-by-case basis.
Therefore, offering patients options wherever possible when observation is required (i.e., bedrooms at night and seclusion rooms) could be considered ethically desirable as part of the obligation of supporting patients’ autonomy, one of the four cardinal principles of biomedical ethics (
30). However, when resources are limited, the principle of autonomy can be in conflict with the principle of distributive justice (
30). Thus administrators and clinicians need to consider carefully whether circumstances permit monitoring options to be made available to patients.
In our view, consent to video monitoring of private spaces should be sought when alternative options are available, in deference to an ethical obligation to respect patients’ autonomy, regardless of whether this is legally required. Once consent is obtained, care should be taken to respect patients’ preferences, which Warr and colleagues (
4) reported did not always occur. For example, staff members sometimes accidentally turned on the wrong camera, which could have resulted in viewing a patient who had not consented, or they used the cameras during daytime and not only at night, as had been agreed upon with patients. This is an example of what Desai (
12) called “function creep”—when camera systems are used for purposes other than what was initially intended and agreed upon. Therefore, Warr and colleagues (
4) suggested that cameras should be covered in rooms of patients who have not given consent to video monitoring. However, respecting the boundaries of patients’ consent and preventing human error can ultimately be achieved only through appropriate training and sensitizing of staff (
4).
For emergencies requiring the use of seclusion or restraint, psychiatric advance directives could provide an opportunity for patients to express their preferences on the type of monitoring desired. We note, however, that use of advance directives is still rare among psychiatric patients (
31), and even when advance directives exist, staff may fail to consult or honor them in crisis situations (
32). Patients’ directives on preferences regarding seclusion or restraint are overridden particularly often (
32), and more work is needed to improve the extent and frequency with which psychiatric advance directives are honored during such episodes (
33).
Privacy and Dignity
Privacy is a major concern with regard to video monitoring in psychiatry (
1–
6,
8,
12), with the majority of commentators agreeing that privacy should be protected as far as possible, albeit with varying definitions of privacy (
34). Privacy can be understood as a moral right that can be deduced from the principle of autonomy (
30), i.e., the right to autonomous control of the dissemination of information about oneself. This approach is reflected in the European Convention of Human Rights, which states that every human being has a “right to respect for his private . . . life” (
35), a right that has been applied specifically to the context of video monitoring in psychiatry (
8). Most legal systems recognize a right to privacy, although the definition of privacy varies widely across jurisdictions (
34). The general notion of privacy has been variously described as a right to be unobserved or undisturbed (
36), not be intruded upon (
34), or simply “to be left alone” (
37). Any form of observation, whether in person or via CCTV, may thus be in tension with this understanding of patient privacy (
4).
Privacy is integral to maintaining one’s self-image and sense of identity, including for psychiatric inpatients (
3). Patients often have a reduced ability to control their self-presentation, particularly in seclusion or restraint, and adding constant video monitoring can lead to a sense of shame, as aspects of self are exposed that the patient would rather have concealed (
3). These concerns are not purely theoretical: in a study by Schütze (
1), 11.3% of patients agreed with the statement that video surveillance is “degrading, inhumane and a breach of my personal rights,” 73.7% disagreed, and 15% expressed no opinion. The constant possibility of being watched can lead people to observe and control themselves in ways that comply with the potential observer’s goals and intentions (
12,
38,
39). Because patients do not know when someone is viewing the images, they have to assume that they could be seen at any time and behave accordingly, assuming they have the capacity to do so (
38). Even if the intention of video surveillance is not to alter behavior but merely to document it, the effects on the patient are the same (
38), including a potential loss of sense of self and personal identity (
3).
To our knowledge, it has not previously been pointed out that installing video cameras comes with a risk of inadvertently introducing constant observation. With traditional observation methods, it is time-consuming to observe a patient constantly, because observation is tied to physical presence. With cameras, this is reversed. It is easier to view a constant video stream as needed or when needed than to turn the camera on and off each and every time it is used to view a patient. Video monitoring indications and duration need to be clearly defined to avoid misuse and to protect patients’ privacy (
3,
4). The duration of observation should be defined on clinical grounds (
3). If only intermittent observation is required, monitoring should not be increased simply because it is technically feasible or easier to leave the camera running constantly.
As noted above, patients have contrasting opinions on the extent to which video monitoring is an intrusion on their privacy, compared with traditional modes of observation (
4). This substantial variance in the impact on patients’ personal sense of privacy and dignity underlines the need to evaluate the use of video monitoring in each individual case and the desirability of seeking consent for its use, when possible (
26).
Saving Recordings
The literature on video surveillance in psychiatry is divided on whether to record and store video recordings of patients. The main arguments in favor of saving videos are that they can provide documentation of incidents for research or serve as evidence in case of allegations of misconduct or for civil or criminal court proceedings (
5,
7,
40). Stolovy and colleagues (
5) stated that “the photographed scene helps to clarify the situation and mitigates any conflict between two versions of the same event.” Videotape evidence has helped to prove the innocence of staff members wrongfully accused of abusing patients (
5,
7). Stolovy and colleagues (
5) also reported a case of abuse by a staff person that had been caught on camera: video footage showed a staff member shoving a patient, which led to the staff member’s dismissal (
5). The usefulness of video recordings in case of conflict needs to be viewed critically. Although videos might well help to clarify what happened, the idea that video recordings can “mitigate any conflict” is almost certainly overstated. After all, videos show only one aspect of reality (
9). Recorded videos often lack a full sequence of events, which may have begun in another space before moving into view of the camera. Crucial actions may be obscured by the positioning of bodies or furniture, and image quality may not be good enough to allow smaller objects, facial expressions, and other key evidence to be identified. Koskela (
9) warned that “people are reduced to doll-like bodies lacking personal qualities, and surveillance is reduced to the observation of bodily movements. The technical equipment that separates the two sides of surveillance makes it difficult for the space to be recognized as a lived, experienced space.”
Further, Desai (
12) argued that if we give too much importance to the questions of establishing blame or fault in our clinical settings, we risk fostering an environment of control and distrust, detracting from an atmosphere of care and communication. In research, video recordings have successfully been used to document and subsequently study inpatient aggression (
7,
40,
41). The authors of one of these studies also found benefit in reviewing footage for clinical or administrative reasons (
7). To date, these potential benefits remain sparsely elucidated, and more research is needed to demonstrate the usefulness of storing video recordings for clinical purposes outside a research setting. What is certain is that storing personally identifiable video recordings of vulnerable patients comes with significant data protection issues (
42). However, the details of data protection and country-specific laws go beyond the scope of this article.