Skip to main content
Open access
REVIEW
Published Online: 10 November 2020

Minds and Brains, Sleep and Psychiatry

Publication: Psychiatric Research and Clinical Practice

Abstract

Objective

This article offers a philosophical thesis for psychiatric disorders that rests upon some simple truths about the mind and brain. Specifically, it asks whether the dual aspect monism—that emerges from sleep research and theoretical neurobiology—can be applied to pathophysiology and psychopathology in psychiatry.

Methods

Our starting point is that the mind and brain are emergent aspects of the same (neuronal) dynamics; namely, the brain–mind. Our endpoint is that synaptic dysconnection syndromes inherit the same dual aspect; namely, aberrant inference or belief updating on the one hand, and a failure of neuromodulatory synaptic gain control on the other. We start with some basic considerations from sleep research that integrate the phenomenology of dreaming with the neurophysiology of sleep.

Results

We then leverage this treatment by treating the brain as an organ of inference. Our particular focus is on the role of precision (i.e., the representation of uncertainty) in belief updating and the accompanying synaptic mechanisms.

Conclusions

Finally, we suggest a dual aspect approach—based upon belief updating (i.e., mind processes) and its neurophysiological implementation (i.e., brain processes)—has a wide explanatory compass for psychiatry and various movement disorders. This approach identifies the kind of pathophysiology that underwrites psychopathology—and points to certain psychotherapeutic and psychopharmacological targets, which may stand in mechanistic relation to each other.

HIGHLIGHTS

The ‘mind’ emerges from Bayesian belief updating in the ‘brain’
Psychopathology can be read as aberrant belief updating.
Aberrant belief updating follows from any neuromodulatory synaptopathy
The mind–brain problem is perpetuated by Cartesian dualism: we tend to think of mind and brain as quintessentially different kinds of things, correlated perhaps, but not two physical aspects of a unified system (1, 2). Working from the perspectives of sleep science and theoretical neurobiology, we have pursued the hypothesis that mind is a brain function (3). This essay attempts to unpack the implications of this bold but thoroughly justified move for medicine in general—and for neurology and psychiatry in particular. Since these considerations arise from the analysis of consciousness, we situate our arguments in that context and tie any clinical conclusions to it. In brief, we address the mind–brain problem from two complementary stances: namely, neurophysiology and theoretical neurobiology.
Our theoretical foundation derives from the work of Hermann von Helmholtz, a neurologically fluent physiologist who first suggested that the brain predicts the consequences of its sensorimotor activity (4, 5, 6). We elaborate the ensuing (free energy) principle in terms of Bayesian inference, which likens the brain–mind to a scientist seeking evidence for her hypotheses (7, 8). In short, our foundational assumption is that consciousness is itself a scientific enterprise (9).
Our neurophysiological foundation regards the brain as a physical system composed of billions of neurons, communicating via electrical and chemical signals—many of which have been rigorously characterized. Neuronal activity gives rise to subjective experience, which is conceived of as a kind of physics. The easiest way to appreciate the relationship of the brain to its mind is to consider the brain as the “material” that responds to biophysical forces and the “mind” as the belief updating driven by the same forces (10).
An early breakthrough in integrative brain–mind science was afforded by the discovery of rapid eye movement (REM) sleep and its concomitant hallucinoid dreaming (11, 12, 13, 14). Control of REM‐dreaming—by chemically specific neurons of the pontine brain stem—established the causal connection between basic neurophysiology and dream phenomenology (13, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 20, 21). Other conscious states, such as waking and non‐REM (NREM) sleep, derive from changes in the same neurophysiological factors. The details of these facts are debated but no‐one contests their importance to the control of conscious processes. We have reviewed the mathematical and neurophysiological foundations of dream phenomenology in a series of previous publications (3, 19, 22). Here, we revisit the conclusions from point of view of psychiatry. In what follows, we briefly review the philosophy and physiology of sleep, with a special focus on lucid dreaming and the activation, input and modulation (AIM) model. In what follows, some terms—like “beliefs”—are used in a technical sense that can depart from their folk psychology meaning. Key terms are listed in a glossary.

Philosophy and Physiology

The radical enlightenment philosopher, Benedict Spinoza, first formulated dual aspect monism in his treatise on Ethics (23). Following Spinoza, we adopt dual aspect monism as follows: the brain–mind is a unified system with two aspects—an objective brain and a subjective mind. We further commit to the notion that there can be no mind in the absence of brain. This eliminates the dualistic assumption of non‐physical causation of mental phenomena. Since both aspects of the brain–mind system are physical, they can be mutually causal. This means that the scientific investigation of the mind is at once the investigation of the brain. From a philosophical perspective, one might argue that Cartesian dualism—as a de facto or legacy position—is still a serious obstacle to progress in consciousness science. Dual aspect monism and its manifold instantiations, some of which are illustrated here, offers a rejection of dualism, enabling a reconstruction of human self‐understanding.
There are many clinical implications of dual aspect monism: for example, (i) “mental illness” becomes a misnomer for psychiatric patients—a misnomer that denies any role for pathophysiology. (ii) A dissolution of the dichotomy between neurology and psychiatry, which divides two fields that belong together. (iii) The psychotic nature of REM‐dreaming; namely, an inherent propensity of the brain–mind for hallucinations and delusions (13, 14, 21, 24). In other words, REM‐dreaming may be viewed as a normal delirium, suggesting that the brain–mind evinces processes that are supposed to be exclusively pathological (25, 26). (iv) Revision of dream theory by viewing the unconscious brain–mind as a predictive model of the world, rather than an escape valve for unacceptable wishes (22). Finally, (v) the potentially potent role of psychotherapy, in resetting the disposition of the brain–mind.

Neurophysiology

The neuronal doctrine of Ramon y Cajal (27) and the reflex doctrine of Charles Sherrington (28) dominated neuroscience from 1890 until about 1950. In the absence of sleep and dream science, Sigmund Freud was unable to complete his Project for a Scientific Psychology in 1895. Instead, he turned his attention to the psychanalytic interpretation of dreams (29), which he insisted was in no way neurological (30). The resulting split in mind‐brain unity had profound effects on medicine, philosophy and psychology. One might contend that this split perpetuated the dualism of Descartes and that Cartesian Dualism continues to divide concepts and fields which ultimately belong together (31).
While psychiatry and neurology proceeded along parallel but separate tracks from the 1890's, neuroscience flourished with the elaboration of principles, such as synaptic action, neurotransmission, and the chemical mediation of neuronal signaling. Only in about 1950 did it became possible to record from individual neurons in living animals (32). A conceptual framework for experimental brain–mind integration was concurrently provided by the discoveries of brain activation in waking (33) and in REM sleep dreaming (34). These discoveries resulted from the technological advance of recording the electrical activity of the brain via the electroencephalogram (EEG) (35).
These neuroscientific advances led to some important insights: The localization of REM sleep control to the pontine brain stem (36), the modulation of cerebral activation by aminergic brain stem neurons (37), the mediation of REM sleep events—including REMs themselves—and the inhibition of motor tonus by specific neurophysiological mechanisms (38). Extracellular neuronal recording produced neurophysiological data from REM sleep that was subsequently integrated with quantitative analysis of dream mentation, to create the first brain‐based theory of dreaming (20, 30). Over the subsequent four decades these findings have been confirmed and enriched (39, 40).

Lucid Dreaming

The psychologist Ursula Voss used EEG to show that when human subjects became aware that they were dreaming—instead of erroneously supposing themselves to be awake as is usual in REM sleep—they exhibited the frontal lobe activation, normally seen in waking—together with parietal and occipital signs of REM sleep (41): see Figure 1. These findings were later supported by a case study using combined EEG and functional magnetic resonance imaging (42), showing heightened BOLD activation in frontal areas, in addition to the precuneus and inferior parietal lobules; all of which are implicit in self‐referential processing and the experience of agency (43).
image
FIGURE 1. Upper panel: Blue and red areas indicate regions typically showing hyperactivation and deactivation, respectively, during REM, relative to waking, as measured by positron emission tomography. Lesions to the parietal operculum are associated with the loss of dreaming following stroke or prefrontal lobotomy. Middle panel: Quantitative electroencephalographic (EEG) studies—comparing brain activity during waking, lucid dreaming and REM sleep—suggest that certain frontal areas are highly activated during waking but show deactivation during REM sleep. During lucid dreaming there is an increase in gamma (40 Hz) power and coherence in frontal areas compared with non‐lucid REM sleep. Scale bars indicate standardized power based on scale potentials (0.50% to 1.50% power). Lower panel: In addition to the increased 40 Hz EEG power in frontal channels, EEG coherence is much higher during lucid dreaming than during non‐lucid REM sleep. EEG coherence during lucid REM sleep corresponds to that during waking (left panel); except for the 8–12 Hz alpha range that shows a peak during waking. CSD, cross‐spectral density. Adapted with permission from (13). REM, rapid eye movement
This finding was supported by a subsequent study showing heightened activity in the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex during dream lucidity (44) and a further study showing elevated resting‐state functional connectivity between the prefrontal and temporoparietal association areas in frequent lucid dreamers (45). Lucid dreaming thus reveals itself to be a hybrid state of the brain–mind, with both waking and dreamlike features—with its phenomenal aspects being reducible to differential activity in specific brain structures (46). This suggests the brain and the mind operate as one, with even the highest features of conscious activity—such as self‐referential processing and insight—having definitive and functionally segregated neuronal correlates.
A related point is that the brain–mind is not necessarily unified with respect to its own cardinal states. The expression “I am of two minds” reflects the ambivalence (or multivalence) of cognition (and emotion) in waking consciousness. The locality of brain activation has been clearly demonstrated in studies of regional cortical activation in NREM sleep (47) and is often referred to as “local” sleep (48, 49, 50). Normal and abnormal conscious experience may thus be not only linked in an intimate way to neuronal dynamics but show the same kind of segregation and differentiation seen in the neurophysiological correlates of sleep (47, 51, 52).

Human REM Sleep Signaling

The Helmholtzian pillar of the current thesis associates unconscious inference with perception and sentience (4, 6). Formal treatments of this notion rest upon predictive processing; namely, using sensory impressions to confirm or disconfirm hypotheses about how our sensory inputs are generated (53). When sensations are generated actively, the accompanying predictions must reflect the way that the sensorium is sampled. Until recently, the electrical encoding of internal predictions that accompany eye movements had only been demonstrated in cats (11, 36). The psychiatrist Charles Hong used brain imaging to demonstrate robust evidence for the existence of these internal stimuli in human REM sleep (54). Each and every human eye movement command—from the pontine brain stem to the forebrain—is associated with information transfer that assures perceptual integrity in waking. And which may be used to construct the visual imagery of dreams. Hong et al (55) have recently discussed these possibilities and how they might be pursued to establish the unity of the brain–mind in visual perception, be it external (as in waking) or internal (as in dreaming). Much of this empirical work was motivated by the AIM model of sleep which we now briefly summarize (see also Figure 2).
image
FIGURE 2. A. Standard sleep polygraphic measurements. These traces show 90−100 min cycles of rapid eye movement (REM) and non‐rapid eye movement (NREM) sleep. The traces show cycles for three subjects, where the blue lines indicate periods of REM sleep. Reports of dreaming are most common from sleep onset stage I (when dreams tend to be fragmentary), late‐night stage II (when dreams tend to be thought‐like) and REM (when they tend to be long, vivid, hallucinatory and bizarre). Deep phases of sleep (III and IV) occur in the first half of the night, whereas lighter stages (stages I and II) predominate in the second half. B. The states of waking and sleep. These states have behavioral, polygraphic and psychological correlates that appear to be orchestrated by a control system in the pontine brainstem. In this panel, the neuronal clock that controls these states is depicted as a reciprocal interaction between inhibitory aminergic neurons and excitatory cholinergic neurons: aminergic activity is highest during waking, declines during NREM sleep and is lowest during REM sleep; whereas cholinergic activity shows the reverse pattern. Changes in sleep phase occur whenever the two activity curves cross; these are also the times when major postural shifts occur. The motor immobility during sleep depends on two different mechanisms: disfacilitation during stages I−IV of NREM sleep and inhibition of motor systems during REM sleep. The motor inhibition during REM sleep prevents motor commands from being executed, so that we do not act out our dreams. C. Human sleep and age. The preponderance of rapid eye movement (REM) sleep in the last trimester of pregnancy and the first year of life decreases progressively as waking time increases. Note that NREM sleep time, like waking time, increases after birth. Despite its early decline, REM sleep continues to occupy approximately 1.5 h/day throughout life. This suggests that its strongest contribution is during neurodevelopment but that it subsequently plays an indispensable role in adulthood. D. The evolution of REM sleep. Birds and mammals evolved separately after branching off from the ancestral tree. Both birds and mammals are homeothermic, and both have appreciable cognitive competence. With respect to the enhancement of cognitive skills by REM, it is significant that both birds and mammals are capable of problem solving and both can communicate verbally. E. AIM model. This panel illustrates normal transitions within the AIM state‐space from waking to NREM and then to REM sleep. The x‐axis represents A (for activation), the y‐axis represents M (for modulation) and the z‐axis represents I (for input–output gating). Waking, NREM sleep and REM sleep occupy distinct loci in this space. Waking and REM sleep have high activation but different I and M values. Thus, in REM sleep, the brain is both off‐line and chemically differentiated compared with the waking brain. NREM sleep is positioned in the center of the space because it is intermediate in all quantitative respects between waking and REM sleep: adapted from (13)

The AIM Model

The activation‐synthesis hypothesis of dreaming (20, 21, 30) and the reciprocal interaction model of sleep cycle control (20) have been modified, simplified and extended to accommodate altered states of consciousness: see Figure 2 and (13). The ensuing AIM account tries to integrate neurophysiology and psychology as follows. The three dimensions of AIM state‐space represent activation (A), input source (I) and modulation (M), as measured neurophysiologically. The discovery of REM‐locked pontine activity in humans (54) enriched the AIM model by providing evidence for human ponto‐geniculo‐occipital (PGO) wave activity (56) that had only been definitively recorded in the pons (57). Figure 3 provides a schematic based on the AIM model in Figure 2 that focuses on the functional anatomy of sleep in terms of neuromodulation. This account is scaffolded on functional brain states and neuromodulation at the level of synaptic physiology, which brings us to the psychopharmacology of sleep—and its intersection with psychopathology.
image
FIGURE 3. The schematic illustrates the neuromodulatory gating of hierarchical message passing in the brain during REM sleep (top panel), wakefulness (right panel) and the hybrid state of lucid dreaming (left panel). The anatomy of this schematic should not be taken too seriously: it is just meant to differentiate between different levels of the cortical hierarchy in terms of low (sensory) levels, intermediate (extrasensory and multimodal) levels and—for the purposes of this essay—high (meta‐representational) levels. Here, we have associated higher levels with theory of mind areas that are engaged in mentalising and perspective taking (and are a component of the default mode). Within each level we have depicted representative cortical microcircuits in terms of superficial (red triangles) and deep (black triangles) pyramidal cells. In predictive coding formulations of neuronal message passing, superficial pyramidal cells encode prediction error that is passed up the hierarchy to update the activity of deep pyramidal cells encoding expectations (red connections). These reciprocate top‐down predictions—that are compared with expectations—by prediction error units in the level below (black connections). In REM sleep, the idea is that cholinergic modulation (blue projections) of superficial pyramidal cells at intermediate levels of the cortical hierarchy preferentially enables these levels, while suppressing ascending prediction errors from primary sensory cortex. In lucid dreaming, aminergic (pink projections) neuromodulation sensitizes prediction errors in the prefrontal cortex, enabling top‐down predictions from the highest deepest levels of the hierarchy—endowing processing in intermediate levels with a narrative or context. In waking, aminergic (e.g., noradrenergic) neuromodulation boosts sensory prediction errors that are now able to entrain hierarchical inference in higher cortical levels for perceptual synthesis. Modified with permission from (62). REM, rapid eye movement
The aminergic and cholinergic neurons that underwrite conscious states are affected by drugs of common use in medicine. These include atropine and the antidepressants (especially the amine reuptake blockers). Because such drugs have both short and long term effects they are useful as sedatives and mood regulators, depending on dose; for example, (58). This is not surprising given the well‐known intimacy of sleep and affect, where the most prominent psychiatric beneficiary of sleep science is mood disorder (59). The reduction in REM sleep latency seen in depression predicts positive response to amine reuptake treatment (60, 61). This speaks to the role of classical ascending modulatory neurotransmitters in the control of both sleep and mood. In the next section, we take some of the above fundaments of sleep and dream science and see how they relate to formulations of the sentient brain, in terms of predictive processing and belief updating. We will see that neuromodulation is a recurring theme that may have a special relevance for psychiatry.

The Phantastic Organ

In this section, we integrate the above themes to show how they underwrite a mechanics of sentience that affords a mechanistic (sic) account of psychopathology and pathophysiology. This account is coarse‐grained but highlights the cross‐cutting themes that link a diverse range of psychiatric and neurological conditions. Our starting point is a commitment to the mind as a brain‐based process; namely, the process of belief updating (6). In this setting, beliefs are used in the sense of Bayesian beliefs or probabilistic representations (7, 8, 63). These are largely of a subpersonal sort, as opposed to propositional beliefs. A central tenet of this formulation of sentience is that it accounts for previous experience (so‐called priors) in the prediction of what causes sensations and consequent behavior.
On this view, mindful processes can be described as inference; that is, inferring the causes of sensations—and indeed acting to elicit sensory information to enable inference. This is a key move in two respects: first, it is necessary when talking about the symptoms, signs and experience of patients, whose phenomenology is quintessentially belief‐based. In other words, nearly all psychiatric syndromes can be framed as aberrant belief updating or false inference. Obvious examples here include hallucinations and delusions; namely, inferring things are there, when they are not (25, 64). Conversely, various forms of agnosia and dissociative syndromes speak to an inference about things that are not present when they are (65, 66). On a statistical reading, these are just two facets of standard inference; referred to as type I and II errors, respectively. The second reason for framing things around inference draws on fluctuating states of consciousness and, in particular, dreaming. If one wanted definitive evidence—phenomenal, physiological, or philosophical—for the brain as a Helmholtz machine or statistical organ, one need look no further than the phenomena of dreaming (3, 19, 24, 40, 67, 68). Dreams evince the remarkable capacity of our brains to generate and construct worlds, even when sequestered from the sensorium, via carefully orchestrated neuromodulatory disconnections (see Figure 3).
The basic idea here is that the brain is a phantastic organ, generating phantasies that it puts to the test—in waking—by using sensory samples from the world (69). However, in dreaming, the fidelity or precision of these sensory inputs is attenuated, enabling a virtual reality to play out in our heads—a process that has been formalized in terms of Bayesian model reduction and complexity minimization (19). The theme of the brain as an organ of prediction now dominates much of cognitive neuroscience in the form of active inference or predictive processing (8, 70, 71, 72). Active inference brings an important (and enactive) aspect to inference; namely, the fact that we actively gather the information upon which inference is based (73). In the current setting, this becomes important when we consider what false inference might look like in an enactive setting. It transpires that several neurological conditions then come under the same explanatory compass; these include Parkinson's disease and other movement disorders associated with synaptopathies (66, 74). To understand this, one has to drill down on a fundamental feature of inference; namely, the encoding or quantification of uncertainty, which we will consider in terms of precision (75, 76, 77).

Precision Psychiatry

There are several ways in which we can license a focus on precision and the encoding of uncertainty in active inference. We will briefly rehearse a few prescient approaches, to show that they all converge on the same conclusion; namely, inference—and especially false inference—depends sensitively on getting precision right (78). Getting precision right depends upon the right deployment of neuromodulatory mechanisms that coordinate message passing in cortical and subcortical hierarchies (76, 79).
First, from a purely technical perspective, a commitment to a dual aspect monism requires the existence of a dual aspect information geometry that links neuronal dynamics to belief updating (10). The technical details are beyond the scope of this essay; however, they can be understood heuristically in terms of two geometries that describe the statistics of neuronal activity (and connectivity) on the one hand, and statistics of (Bayesian) beliefs encoded by that activity (and connectivity) on the other. In other words, there are two information geometries that inherit from the ensemble dynamics of neuronal populations. The first pertains to the probabilistic evolution of neuronal states, while the second pertains to the evolution (i.e., updating) of beliefs about something—beliefs that are encoded by neuronal states (and connectivity). Crucially, these two information geometries arise in any system that self‐organizes itself in a way that can be separated from its environment (80, 81, 82).
This may sound rather abstract; however, it is just a statement of a fact—for which we are our own existence proof. Namely, the neurophysiology and neurochemistry of our brains conforms to the laws of thermodynamics and an associated information geometry (83). At the same time, these physiological states (c.f., the AIM model) are necessarily equipped with an information geometry that pertains to things and narratives “out there.” Dreaming is a beautiful example of this: my brain enters a particular sleep (e.g., REM) state, characterized by a particular physiology, while at the same time I dream about things in my lived world. Crucially, the things I dream about are essentially grounded in my navigation of that world. In other words, REM dreams are always animated (hence in the service of running motor programs offline), emotional (with anxiety, aggression, and elation predominating), bizarre (meaning only remotely associative) and so on (13, 84). “Chase” dreams are common and well‐known, and frequently overlap with—and merge—into nightmares. In the dream state, one rehearses threatening situations (running away, turning, and fighting) but also simulates more abstract potentialities. One can fly or make love (85), particularly when lucid (86).

An Intuitive Physics for the Mind

Technically, information geometries underwrite a (Bayesian) mechanics of the self‐organizing brain and thereby characterize the nature of belief spaces (82). This can be appreciated from a number of complementary perspectives. For example, one can apply gauge theoretic treatments (87). Alternatively, one can think about the notion of distance and information length—as measures of how far beliefs move during inference or belief updating (83, 88). All these treatments converge on the same quantity; namely, the precision of beliefs—that is, the confidence or inverse variance of a belief distribution.
Information geometry allows us to conceive of belief‐spaces in which two beliefs are equipped with a measure of distance between them. The key notion here is some state‐space (e.g., the physiological states of the AIM model), where every point in this space corresponds to a Bayesian belief (i.e., a probability distribution). This special sort of state‐space is called a statistical manifold. For example, imagine I saw something fluttering out of the corner of my eye. On foveating the source of “fluttering,” I “see” it is a butterfly. This active sampling of the visual scene moves my (prior) beliefs that there was a small creature out there—with probability mass distributed over all kinds of plausible alternatives (e.g., insect, bird, leaf, etc.)—to a precise (posterior) belief (e.g., butterfly). This belief updating corresponds to moving from one point on a statistical manifold to another. So, what are the key determinants of that movement and how is movement on a statistical manifold measured?
In statistics, this measure is based on the Fisher information metric. Under mild (i.e., Gaussian) assumptions, this metric corresponds to the precision or confidence associated with (probabilistic or posterior) beliefs. Intuitively, we can envisage a myriad of beliefs occupying some belief space, all attracting each other to a greater or lesser degree. This is very much like a celestial n‐body problem, in which heavenly bodies, pull each other in different directions—to find their minimum free energy configuration. In this intuitive physics, precision corresponds to the mass of each belief (or associated prediction error). In other words, a belief (or associated prediction error) that is afforded greater precision will behave like a massive body—attracting smaller beliefs to it—and becoming relatively impervious to others. For example, if sensory precision were inordinately high, believes based upon sensory evidence would acquire a gravity that pull other (empirical prior) beliefs towards it. This attraction is the manifestation of (mindful) forces that underwrite belief updating from prior to posterior Bayesian beliefs, that is, before and after the effects of sensory forces. Conversely, if prior precision is high the forces exerted by sensory impressions exert less influence on beliefs deep within a hierarchical belief system. These two extremes are just the difference between waking and sleep, respectively; in waking we have information from the outside world to shape perception, whereas in sleep, we are sequestered from these sensory impressions.
On this view, one can see how getting precision right becomes crucial: precision is the glue, or bridge that realizes conditional dependencies among distinct beliefs about the lived world. If this coupling were to fail, there would literally be a disintegration of the psyche and loss of central (deep) coherence that characterizes conditions like schizophrenia and autism (89, 90, 91, 92). Indeed, as we will see below, any form of belief updating must have precision at its heart, suggesting that psychopathology is a pathology of precision.

Predictive Processing and Precision

From the perspective of predictive coding (a canonical scheme for predictive processing) (93, 94), precision is the key quantity that coordinates belief updating by differentially weighting prediction errors as they ascend cortical hierarchies (75, 95, 96, 97, 98, 99). In these schemes, prediction errors represent the difference between sensory input and top‐down predictions of that input. Any mismatch then revises Bayesian beliefs or expectations encoded by neuronal activity to implement belief updating—and provide better predictions that resolve prediction errors (see Figure 3). In engineering, precision is known as Kalman gain (100) and scores the precision or reliability of prediction errors; such that only precise prediction errors have access to higher levels of belief updating (101). In this setting, it can be seen that getting the precision or gain right is crucial for veridical inference.
From a physiological perspective, precision is thought to be encoded in the synaptic gain or excitability of particular neuronal populations (e.g., superficial pyramidal cells encoding prediction errors). It can be subsumed under notions of excitation‐inhibition balance or cortical gain control at the population level (102, 103). At the synaptic level, it encompasses a broad range of neuromodulatory mechanisms that generally involve fast‐spiking inhibitory interneurons that Interact with pyramidal cells (104, 105, 106, 107, 108). In turn, these (often synchronous) interactions depend upon N‐methyl‐D‐aspartate (NMDA) receptor function and, crucially, classical ascending modulatory neurotransmitter systems (e.g., noradrenaline, serotonin, and acetylcholine) (109, 110).
From a psychological perspective, precision manifests as various forms of attentional gain control or selection (101, 111). The right deployment of sensory precision in the visual domain can be thought of as mediating spatial attention, whereas higher in the hierarchy it can be associated with feature attention and, possibly, internal attention states (112, 113).
It is at this point that we see the formal relationship between precision and the AIM model (21). The activation (A) of certain neuronal populations—that entail belief updating—depends upon their input (I), which is under modulatory control (M). The permissive requirements for sleep rest upon a selective disconnection of sensory inputs via aminergic neuromodulation, which can be thought of as a physiologically mediated inattention to the sensorium. In many respects, it is the exact complement of mindfulness, in which sustained attention to a specific sensory input is maintained (114).
Finally, from a more philosophical perspective, the hierarchical control or predictions of precision underwrite notions of mental action and the distinction between the phenomenal transparency and capacity (68, 115, 116, 117). When associated with interoceptive inference, high level representations—that themselves predict the precision of lower‐level representations—may have a crucial role in emotional inference and elaborating a minimal selfhood (98, 115, 118).
In summary, a ubiquitous and key aspect of belief updating, or active inference, is the mechanics of encoding uncertainty, by optimizing (Bayesian) beliefs about precision. Mechanistically, this speaks to a key role of neuromodulation and the context‐sensitive control of synaptic efficacy. Psychologically, it ties in attention to any consideration of mindful processing (i.e., inference). Finally, these mechanisms are evinced most powerfully by the greatest contrast of sentience we know; namely, the difference between waking perception and dreaming. We now turn to aberrant precision in neuropsychiatry.

Aberrant Precision

In the past years, nearly every psychiatric condition has been considered under the lens of precision; ranging from autism through to schizophrenia; from tremor through to Parkinson's disease; from obsessive‐compulsive disorder through to post‐traumatic stress disorder; from depression through to chronic stress; from fatigue through to functional medical symptoms (65, 97, 119, 120, 121, 122, 123, 124, 125, 126, 127, 128, 129, 130). Table 1 provides a selective survey of some key publications, all pivoting on aberrant precision control. Each entry in Table 1 deserves its own discussion, showing how the same fundamental deficit in aberrant precision or attentional processing can manifest in domains as diverse as motor control to depersonalization. In what follows, we will focus on a couple of cardinal examples.
TABLE 1. A selection of recent papers dealing with predictive coding, precision and psychiatry
Syndrome symptomSelected papers
Precision, predictive coding and Bayesian inference in schizorpheniaPollak TA, Corlett PR. Blindness, psychosis, and the visual Construction of the world. Schizophr Bull. 2019 Oct 11. pii: sbz098. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbz098. [Epub ahead of print]
 Benrimoh et al. (2019) (135)
 Sterzer et al. (2018) (158)
 Dzafic I, Burianová H, Martin AK, Mowry B. Neural correlates of dynamic emotion perception in schizophrenia and the influence of prior expectations. Schizophr Res. 2018 Dec; 202:129–137
 Heinz A, Murray GK, Schlagenhauf F, Sterzer P, Grace AA, Waltz JA. Towards a Unifying cognitive, neurophysiological, and computational neuroscience account of schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2019 Sep 11; 45 (5):1092–1100
 Limongi R, Bohaterewicz B, Nowicka M, Plewka A, Friston KJ. Knowing when to stop: Aberrant precision and evidence accumulation in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2018 Jul; 197:386–391
 Randeniya R, Oestreich LKL, Garrido MI. Sensory prediction errors in the continuum of psychosis. Schizophr Res. 2017 Apr 27. pii: S0920‐9964 (17)30206‐2
 Griffin JD, Fletcher PC. Predictive processing, source monitoring, and psychosis. Annu Rev Clin Psychol. 2017 May 8; 13:265–289
 Corlett PR. I predict, Therefore I Am: Perturbed predictive coding under ketamine and in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry. 2017 Mar 15; 81 (6):465–466
 Tschacher W, Giersch A, Friston K. Embodiment and schizophrenia: A review of implications and applications. Schizophr Bull. 2017 Mar 3
 van Schalkwyk GI, Volkmar FR, Corlett PR. A predictive coding account of psychotic symptoms in autism spectrum disorder. J Autism Dev Disord. 2017 May; 47 (5):1323–1340
 Schmack K, Rothkirch M, Priller J, Sterzer P. Enhanced predictive signalling in schizophrenia. Hum Brain Mapp. 2017 Apr; 38 (4):1767–1779
 Sterzer P, Mishara AL, Voss M, Heinz A. Thought Insertion as a self‐Disturbance: An integration of predictive coding and Phenomenological approaches. Front Hum Neurosci. 2016 Oct 12; 10:502. eCollection 2016
 Kort NS, Ford JM, Roach BJ, Gunduz‐Bruce H, Krystal JH, Jaeger J, Reinhart RM, Mathalon DH. Role of N‐Methyl‐D‐Aspartate receptors in action‐based predictive coding deficits in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry. 2017 Mar 15; 81 (6):514–524
 Friston K, Brown HR, Siemerkus J, Stephan KE. The dysconnection hypothesis (2016). Schizophr Res. 2016 Oct; 176 (2‐3):83–94
 Roa Romero Y, Keil J, Balz J, Gallinat J, Senkowski D. Reduced frontal theta oscillations indicate altered crossmodal prediction error processing in schizophrenia. J Neurophysiol. 2016 Sep 1; 116 (3):1396–1407
 Wacongne C. A predictive coding account of MMN reduction in schizophrenia. Biol Psychol. 2016 Apr; 116:68–74
 Powers et al. (2015) (136)
 Adams RA, Huys QJ, Roiser JP. Computational psychiatry: Towards a mathematically informed understanding of mental illness. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 2016 Jan; 87 (1):53–63
 Rentzsch J, Shen C, Jockers‐Scherübl MC, Gallinat J, Neuhaus AH. Auditory mismatch negativity and repetition suppression deficits in schizophrenia explained by irregular computation of prediction error. PLoS One. 2015 May 8; 10 (5):e0126775
 Castelnovo A, Ferrarelli F, D'Agostino A. Schizophrenia: From neurophysiological abnormalities to clinical symptoms. Front Psychol. 2015 Apr 20; 6:478
 Notredame et al. (2014) (137)
 Fogelson et al. (2014) (149)
 Horga G, Schatz KC, Abi‐Dargham A, Peterson BS. Deficits in predictive coding underlie hallucinations in schizophrenia. J Neurosci. 2014 Jun 11; 34 (24):8072–8082
 Jardri R, Denève S. Circular inferences in schizophrenia. Brain. 2013 Nov; 136(Pt 11):3227–3241
 Ford JM, Palzes VA, Roach BJ, Mathalon DH. Did I do that? Abnormal predictive processes in schizophrenia when button pressing to deliver a tone. Schizophr Bull. 2014 Jul; 40 (4):804–812
 Adams et al. (2013) (138)
 Nazimek JM, Hunter MD, Woodruff PW. Auditory hallucinations: Expectation‐perception model. Med Hypotheses. 2012 Jun; 78 (6):802–810
 Lalanne L, van Assche M, Giersch A. When predictive mechanisms go wrong: Disordered visual synchrony thresholds in schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2012 May; 38 (3):506–513
Precision, predictive coding and Bayesian inference in autism and autistic spectrum disorderLanillos P, Oliva D, Philippsen A, Yamashita Y, Nagai Y, Cheng G. A review on neural network models of schizophrenia and autism spectrum disorder. Neural Netw. 2019 Nov 13; 122:338–363
 Van de Cruys S, Perrykkad K, Hohwy J. Explaining hyper‐sensitivity and hypo‐responsivity in autism with a common predictive coding‐based mechanism. Cogn Neurosci. 2019 Jul; 10 (3):164–166
 Lawson et al. (2017) (133)
 Chambon V, Farrer C, Pacherie E, Jacquet PO, Leboyer M, Zalla T. Reduced sensitivity to social priors during action prediction in adults with autism spectrum disorders. Cognition. 2017 Mar; 160:17–26
 van Schalkwyk GI, Volkmar FR, Corlett PR. A predictive coding account of psychotic symptoms in autism spectrum disorder. J Autism Dev Disord. 2017 May; 47 (5):1323–1340
 Van de Cruys S, Van der Hallen R, Wagemans J. Disentangling signal and noise in autism spectrum disorder. Brain Cogn. 2017 Mar; 112:78–83
 Manning C, Kilner J, Neil L, Karaminis T, Pellicano E. Children on the autism spectrum update their behaviour in response to a volatile environment. Dev Sci. 2016 Aug 6. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/desc.12435
 Chan JS, Langer A, Kaiser J. Temporal integration of multisensory stimuli in autism spectrum disorder: a Predictive coding perspective. J Neural Transm (Vienna). 2016 Aug; 123 (8):917–923
 von der Lühe T, Manera V, Barisic I, Becchio C, Vogeley K, Schilbach L. Interpersonal predictive coding, not action perception, is impaired in autism. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2016 May 5; 371 (1693)
 Gonzalez‐Gadea ML, Chennu S, Bekinschtein TA, Rattazzi A, Beraudi A, Tripicchio P, Moyano B, Soffita Y, Steinberg L, Adolfi F, Sigman M, Marino J, Manes F, Ibanez A. Predictive coding in autism spectrum disorder and attention deficit hyperactivity disorder. J Neurophysiol. 2015 Nov; 114 (5):2625–2636
 Palmer CJ, Seth AK, Hohwy J. The felt presence of other minds: Predictive processing, counterfactual predictions, and mentalising in autism. Conscious Cogn. 2015 Nov; 36:376–389
Precision, predictive coding and Bayesian inference in depression, stress and anxietyLinson A, Parr T, Friston KJ. Active inference, stressors, and psychological trauma: A neuroethological model of (mal)adaptive explore‐exploit dynamics in ecological context. Behav Brain Res. 2019 Dec 9; 380:112421
 Kube T, Schwarting R, Rozenkrantz L, Glombiewski JA, Rief W. Distorted cognitive processes in major depression: A predictive processing perspective. Biol Psychiatry. 2019 Jul 29. pii: S0006‐3223 (19)31550‐1
 Adams RA, Huys QJ, Roiser JP. Computational psychiatry: Towards a mathematically informed understanding of mental illness. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 2016 Jan; 87 (1):53–63
 Clark et al. (2018) (128)
 Adam Linson, Karl Friston. Reframing PTSD for computational psychiatry with the active inference framework. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. 2019; 24 (5): 347–368
 Barrett LF, Quigley KS, Hamilton P. An active inference theory of allostasis and interoception in depression. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2016 Nov 19; 371 (1708). pii: 20160011
 Seth and Friston (2016) (97)
 Stephan et al. (2016) (129)
 Schutter DJ. A Cerebellar framework for predictive coding and Homeostatic Regulation in depressive disorder. Cerebellum. 2016 Feb; 15 (1):30–33
 Chekroud (2015) (168)
 Cornwell et al. (2017) (127)
 Kim MJ, Shin J, Taylor JM, Mattek AM, Chavez SJ, Whalen PJ. Intolerance of uncertainty predicts increased Striatal volume. Emotion. 2017 May 18
 Trapp S, Kotz SA. Predicting Affective information ‐ an evaluation of Repetition Suppression effects. Front Psychol. 2016 Sep 9; 7:1365
 Garfinkel SN, Seth AK, Barrett AB, Suzuki K, Critchley HD. Knowing your own heart: Distinguishing interoceptive accuracy from interoceptive awareness. Biol Psychol. 2015 Jan; 104:65–74
 Lawson RP, Rees G, Friston KJ. An aberrant precision account of autism. Front Hum Neurosci. 2014 May 14; 8:302
Precision, predictive coding and Bayesian inference in hallucinations and hallucinosisPowers AR, Corlett PR, Ross DA. Guided by Voices: Hallucinations and the psychosis spectrum. Biol Psychiatry. 2018 Sep 15; 84 (6):e43–e45
 Powers et al. (2017) (64)
 Corlett PR, Horga G, Fletcher PC, Alderson‐day B, Schmack K, powers AR 3rd. Hallucinations and Strong priors. Trends Cogn Sci. 2019 Feb; 23 (2):114–127
 Sterzer et al. (2018) (158)
 O'Callaghan C, Hall JM, Tomassini A, Muller AJ, Walpola IC, Moustafa AA, Shine JM, Lewis SJG.Visual hallucinations are characterized by Impaired sensory evidence Accumulation: Insights from hierarchical Drift Diffusion modeling in Parkinson's disease. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimaging. 2017 Nov; 2 (8):680–688
 Sterzer P, Mishara AL, Voss M, Heinz A. Thought Insertion as a self‐Disturbance: An integration of predictive coding and Phenomenological approaches. Front Hum Neurosci. 2016 Oct 12; 10:502
 Powers AR III, Kelley M, Corlett PR. Hallucinations as top‐down effects on perception. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimaging. 2016 Sep; 1 (5):393–400
 Griffin JD, Fletcher PC. Predictive processing, source monitoring, and psychosis. Annu Rev Clin Psychol. 2017 May 8; 13:265–289
 Schmack K, Rothkirch M, Priller J, Sterzer P. Enhanced predictive signalling in schizophrenia. Hum Brain Mapp. 2017 Apr; 38 (4):1767–1779
 Sterzer P, Mishara AL, Voss M, Heinz A. Thought Insertion as a self‐Disturbance: An integration of predictive coding and Phenomenological approaches. Front Hum Neurosci. 2016 Oct 12; 10:502
 Roa Romero Y, Keil J, Balz J, Gallinat J, Senkowski D. Reduced frontal theta oscillations indicate altered crossmodal prediction error processing in schizophrenia. J Neurophysiol. 2016 Sep 1; 116 (3):1396–1407
 Teufel C, Subramaniam N, Dobler V, Perez J, Finnemann J, Mehta PR, Goodyer IM, Fletcher PC. Shift toward prior knowledge confers a perceptual advantage in early psychosis and psychosis‐prone healthy individuals. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2015 Oct 27; 112 (43):13401–13406
 Powers et al. (2015) (136)
The thesis developed here helps clarify why the AIM model translates so gracefully when describing psychopathology and other disorders of movement and perception. This follows from the simple observation that if psychology (i.e., the mind) and physiology (i.e., the brain) inherit from the same (Bayesian) mechanics, it follows that psychopathology must be a pathology of inference. The particular kind of false inference—implied by the key role of precision—is then grounded in synaptic gain control that selects the sensory inputs (and, in predictive coding, ascending prediction errors throughout cortical hierarchies) responsible for inference or belief updating. This immediately suggests that any pathophysiology that can be framed as a synaptopathy, which interferes with synaptic gain control, can be understood in terms of aberrant precision control (131). We will focus on a couple of canonical examples to illustrate the crosscutting themes.
Perhaps the poster child for this line of thinking is autism, in which the belief updating has been proposed to rest on an imbalance between sensory evidence and prior beliefs—mediated by their relative precision (91, 132, 133, 134). The synaptic mechanisms that underwrite this imbalance are much less well developed but a compelling story can still be told at the level of psychopathology. Schizophrenia, has, arguably, the more advanced story—of abnormal synaptic gain control—to accompany the concomitant failures of belief updating and inference (64, 125, 135, 136, 137, 138, 139, 140). As with many psychiatric syndromes, the story starts with a failure of sensory attenuation—in the sense of a failure to modulate sensory precision (141, 142, 143, 144, 145, 146, 147). This explains some key soft neurological signs in schizophrenia such as an attenuation of the mismatch negativity, failures of slow pursuit eye movements and failures of sensory attenuation that underlie the force matching illusion (138).
In many instances, these examples demonstrate a paradoxical veracity of perception that renders it difficult to elicit illusions in schizophrenia (137, 148). The evidence for this kind of (paradoxical) deficit usually rests upon a careful use of psychophysics and computational modeling to illustrate aberrant precision control; for example (149). The physiological concomitants are easily articulated in terms of neuronal processing (e.g., abnormal excitation‐inhibition balance) (150), right down to the receptors that may mediate this control (e.g., NMDA receptors and GABAergic neurotransmission) (103, 110, 136, 151, 152, 153, 154, 155, 156, 157, 158). In this sense, schizophrenia may be a paradigm example of a (synaptic) disconnection syndrome that is largely manifest in terms of abnormal perception and belief updating (i.e., hallucinations and delusions). If this is the right story, then one would expect to see very similar phenomenology in other conditions that compromise synaptic gain control. Key examples here are synaptopathies; for example, Lewy body disease leading to hallucinosis (25, 159).
One key question in schizophrenia research, in this setting, is the emergence of delusions—which at first glance seem a prime candidate for high‐level belief systems that are afforded “too much” precision. This appears to fly in the face of a failure of sensory attenuation (i.e., too much sensory precision). Although consensus has not yet emerged, this might be an interesting example of a (perceptual) paradoxical lesion (160, 161, 162). In other words, a synaptopathy at higher levels of cortical (hierarchical) processing that partially reverses the effects of a primary insult at the sensory level. In other words, a compensatory increase in precision of higher level belief systems may be necessary to balance a loss of attenuation at lower levels; thereby engendering delusional belief systems as the best Bayesian explanation for sensory evidence—that one has lost the capacity to ignore. This clearly has close relationships with earlier notions, such as the aberrant salience hypothesis (163, 164) and fits nicely with the effects of psychedelic and psychomimetic drugs (165).
From a practical point of view, the foregoing suggests that pharmacotherapy—targeting neuromodulatory systems—is exactly the right way to proceed. Having said this, the multiple factors involved in synaptic gain control make psychopharmacology a challenging avenue to remediate a loss of delicate balance in hierarchical neuronal message passing. On a more positive note, if one subscribes to the above story, then the top‐down control of precision weighting becomes another therapeutic target. In this sense, it speaks to the possibility of using psychotherapy in conjunction with psychopharmacology (166, 167, 168), to improve a patient's ability to orchestrate the many facets of attention.
In concluding this section, we briefly consider movement disorders. The link between movement disorders and false inference is mandated by active inference accounts of how we sample our world. There are many examples here; for example, the difficulties schizophrenic patients have with slow pursuit eye movements (125, 169). Perhaps a more fanciful example would be Parkinson's disease. However, the inferential (mindful) mechanics could be exactly the same as seen in other conditions ranging from alpha synucleinopathies (76, 158, 170) through to autonomic dysfunction (123, 171).
The idea here is that our motor and autonomic reflexes are just in the service of fulfilling top‐down predictions (97). This tenet of active inference inherits from ideomotor theories and 20th‐century formulations such as equilibrium point hypothesis (172) and perceptual control theory and the passive movement paradigm (173, 174). In brief, if all our (motor and autonomic) actions are realizations of descending (proprioceptive and interoceptive) predictions, then the precision afforded descending predictions, relative to the peripheral prediction errors that drive reflexes, becomes crucial. Indeed, Parkinson's disease could be regarded as a complete failure to attenuate proprioceptive precision, such that the intention to move is immediately subverted on the basis of (unattenuated) proprioceptive evidence one is not moving (138). The neuromodulatory correlates—on an active inference reading of motor control—of this putative failure are well characterized in terms of dopamine neurotransmission (175)—and, indeed, the electrophysiological correlates of precision control such as beta activity (176).

Summary

In summary, a broad range of psychiatric and neurological disorders may yield to a coarse‐grained but mechanistic explanation in terms of aberrant precision control. Crucially, the mechanics at hand are of two sorts. On the one hand, there is the Bayesian mechanics of belief updating, which underwrites our perceptions and experience of the world—and how it is actively sampled—on the other hand, the synaptic mechanisms are, at a physiological, computational and population level, clearly situated in terms of their role in belief updating. In short, the encoding of uncertainty or precision in the brain inherits from a dual aspect monism.

Discussion

In the foregoing, we have appealed to the fundaments of sleep research; both in terms of its implications for sentience and its neurophysiology to argue for a holistic framing of neuropsychiatric disorders that dissolves Cartesian dualism by treating mindful processes (i.e., belief updating) and neuronal processes (i.e., synaptic physiology) as two sides of the same coin. One could of course consider disorders cortical gain (i.e., precision) control and, indeed, sleep per se within this framework.
A particularly instructive example is the rich history of seizure disorder. Excitability is an intrinsic and essential aspect of neuronal electrical function (103, 150, 177, 178, 179), but it also constitutes a natural problem because that excitability must be controlled (180)—and this control has been considered in relation to precision (181). The brain–mind is particularly vulnerable to escape from excitability control (71). Epileptic seizures are the result when local foci of seizure discharge become generalized. The pathophysiology of epilepsy and the normal occurrence of paroxysmal neuronal firing in REM sleep have been detailed elsewhere (182). Here, we focus on two related themes: temporal lobe epilepsy and normal dreaming.
In temporal lobe epilepsy, a hyperexcitable focus arises in the limbic brain and spreads so as to take over waking consciousness. An affected subject becomes suspicious to the point of paranoia, convinced that others are talking about them, and harboring delusions of self‐importance. Great writers like Fyodor Dostoyevsky may have had hyperexcitable temporal lobes which drove their creative, and some would say, “hypergraphic” literary productivity (183).
A more physiological temporal lobe stimulation occurs in REM sleep dreaming. Four or five times a night the brainstem sends excitatory signals to the temporal lobe such that we see, hear and feel sensations and emotions not entirely unlike those of the epileptic patient. Are we to suppose that dreaming is pathological? No, but we might consider the kinship of our normal brain–mind state to the psychosis of people we call patients. Our understanding of their hallucinations and delusions makes discussion of these so‐called symptoms more direct and naturalistic. “Your visions are like my dreams” we might say. This statement is more than reassuring.
Abundant neurophysiological findings of REM abnormalities in psychiatric patients (184, 185, 186), further support the notion that psychopathology and inference have a common grounding in neuromodulatory control that transcends waking and sleeping. Furthermore, evidence of NREM sleep alterations, including deficits in sleep spindles and slow waves, have been increasingly reported in neuropsychiatric disorders, especially in patients with schizophrenia (185, 187, 188, 189, 190, 191), implicating these electrophysiological correlates of sleep in the pathophysiology of these disorders; particularly in the consolidation or learning usually associated with NREM sleep (50).
The state dependency of vital functions is illustrated by the cessation of breathing in sleep due to neuronal deactivation in the brainstem (192, 193), pointing to the role of ascending modulatory neurotransmitter systems in the control of breathing and the generation of central apneas. Furthermore, when aggravated by age or obesity, the obstructive sleep apnea may become gravely disabling and even fatal (194). The understanding of sleep disorders may be informed by a pathophysiological approach that integrates clinical and basic biological science (195). For the mind–brain integrationist this—and other sleep disorders—provide an interdisciplinary bridge for neurologists, psychiatrists and internists. The oxygen dependence of the brain–mind is further testimony to the physical basis of waking, sleeping, and dreaming. Fortunately, sleep apnea can be treated by the application of positive airway pressure and when nocturnal brain–mind anoxia is reduced, normal waking cognition is typically restored (196).
Vital functions underwrite (and inform) belief updating from the subpersonal and interoceptive to the propositional and prosocial. This speaks to the importance of communication and psychotherapy. It is the whole brain–mind that is the target of psychotherapy. And it is sensitive to what is said. Psychological intervention is thus seen to be qualitatively akin to neurosurgery but has the twin advantages of having no structurally damaging side effects and a more global reach. This concept should delight all practitioners of talking treatment. Psychotherapy is a physical modality.
A caveat is that therapeutic efficacy must remain the gold standard of all patient treatment. It is clear that cognitive behavior therapy is the treatment of choice for most phobias—and insurance systems are wise to license it because of its efficiency and efficaciousness. But individuals of private means, who wish to investigate the psychodynamic nature of their family experience, may expect no lesser causal effects on their world view from analytically oriented psychotherapy. In fact, psychoanalytic psychotherapy may now transcend Freud's own adherence to Cartesian dualism; at the same time, the brain–mind concept fulfills his abandoned goal for a scientific psychology.

Limitations

AIM is a preliminary model, which should be regarded as a demonstration project. Its limitations with respect to the many already well‐known alterations of conscious state have been emphasized previously. One must also appreciate the anatomical problems associated with regional brain differentiation. To be true to reality, AIM—or its derivatives—should describe brain–mind conditions at all scales, not just at the level of the whole system. Is consciousness really a winner‐take‐all phenomenon or does it consist of multiple substrates, each with its own AIM? And speaking of AIM, are three dimensions adequate to define state‐space? Almost certainly not. Skeptics ask for many more and nay‐sayers believe the brain–mind problem to be beyond the reach of science. Others may consider themselves to be descendants of Lucretius, Aristotle—or even Spinoza—and there is a clear invitation to join in this glorious conceit.

Footnotes

Karl J. Friston is funded by the Wellcome Trust (Ref: 088130/Z/09/Z). We would also like to thank our anonymous reviews for helpful guidance in writing this essay.
The authors declare no conflict of interest.
[Corrections added on November 26, 2020 after first online publication: 1. The first author's name has been corrected, and 2. The text “blood oxygenation level‐dependent (BOLD)” has been corrected as “bold” in the first paragraph of the article.]

REFERENCES

1.
Chalmers DJ: The meta‐problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 2018; 25:6–61
2.
Chalmers D: Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 1995; 2:200–219
3.
Hobson JA, Friston KJ: Consciousness, dreams, and inference the Cartesian theatre revisited. J Conscious Stud. 2014; 21:6–32
4.
Helmholtz H: Concerning the perceptions in general; in Treatise on physiological optics. New York, NY, Dover; 1866/ 1962
5.
Von Helmholtz H: Handbuch der physiologischen Optik. Leipzig, Germany: Voss, 1867
6.
Helmholtz H: The facts of perception: in The Selected Writings of Hermann von Helmholtz. Edited by Middletown RK. Connecticut, Wesleyan University Press, 1878(1971). p. 384
7.
Dayan P, Hinton GE, Neal RM, et al: The Helmholtz machine. Neural Comput. 1995; 7:889–904
8.
Friston K: The free‐energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat Rev Neurosci. 2010; 11:127–138
9.
Bruineberg J, Kiverstein J, Rietveld E: The anticipating brain is not a scientist: the free‐energy principle from an ecological‐enactive perspective. Synthese. 2018; 195:2417–2444
10.
Friston KJ, Wiese W, Hobson JA: Sentience and the origins of consciousness: From cartesian duality to Markovian monism. Entropy. 2020; 22:516. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22050516
11.
Nelson JP, McCarley R, Hobson JA: REM sleep burst neurons, PGO waves, and eye movement information. J Neurophysiol. 1983; 50:784–797
12.
Walker MP, Stickgold R: Sleep‐dependent learning and memory consolidation. Neuron. 2004; 44:121–133
13.
Hobson JA: REM sleep and dreaming: towards a theory of protoconsciousness. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2009; 10:803–813
14.
Tononi G: Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto. Biol Bull. 2008; 215:216–242
15.
Calvo J, Datta S, Quattrochi J, et al: Cholinergic microstimulation of the peribrachial nucleus in the cat. II. Delayed and prolonged increases in REM sleep. Arch Ital Biol. 1992; 130:285–301
16.
Alam MN, McGinty D, Szymusiak R: Neuronal discharge of preoptic/anterior hypothalamic thermosensitive neurons: relation to NREM sleep. Am J Physiol. 1995; 269:R1240–1249
17.
Silberman EK, Vivaldi E, Garfield J, et al: Carbachol triggering of desynchronized sleep phenomena: enhancement via small volume infusions. Brain Res. 1980; 191:215–224
18.
Datta S, Calvo JM, Quattrochi J, et al: Cholinergic microstimulation of the peribrachial nucleus in the cat. I. Immediate and prolonged increases in ponto‐geniculo‐occipital waves. Arch Ital Biol. 1992; 130:263–284
19.
Hobson JA, Friston KJ: Waking and dreaming consciousness: neurobiological and functional considerations. Prog Neurobiol. 2012; 98:82–98
20.
McCarley RW, Hobson JA: Neuronal excitability modulation over the sleep cycle: a structural and mathematical model. Science. 1975; 189:58–60
21.
Hobson JA: The AIM Model of Dreaming, Sleeping, and Waking Consciousness Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, 2009; 963–970. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-008045046-9.00042-5
22.
Hobson JA, Friston KJ: A response to our theatre critics. J Conscious Stud. 2016; 23:245–254
23.
Spinoza BD: The ethics, Part I. Champaign, Ill. Leipzig, Germany, Project Gutenberg, 1999
24.
Seth AK: A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia. Cogn Neurosci. 2014; 5:97–118
25.
Collerton D, Perry E, McKeith I: Why people see things that are not there: a novel Perception and Attention Deficit model for recurrent complex visual hallucinations. Behav Brain Sci. 2005; 28:737–757
26.
Hobson JA: Dreaming as Delirium. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press, 1999
27.
Bullock TH, Bennett MV, Johnston D, et al: Neuroscience. The neuron doctrine. Redux Sci. 2005; 310:791–793
28.
Burke RE: Sir Charles Sherrington's the integrative action of the nervous system: a centenary appreciation. Brain. 2007; 130:887–894
29.
Freud S: The Interpretation of Dreams; and on Dreams: (1900‐1901). London, UK, Hogarth Press : Institute of Psycho‐Analysis, 1995
30.
Hobson JA, McCarley RW: The brain as a dream state generator: an activation‐synthesis hypothesis of the dream process. Am J Psychiatry. 1977; 134:1335–1348
31.
Damasio A: Descartes' Error: Emotion Reason and the Human Brain. Putnam Publishing, 1994, hardcover: ISBN 0-399-13894-3
32.
Gerard RW: Mirror to Physiology. New York, NY, Springer New York, 1958
33.
Moruzzi G, Magoun HW: Brain stem reticular formation and activation of the EEG. Electroencephalogr Clin Neurophysiol. 1949; 1:455–473
34.
Aserinsky E, Kleitman N: Regularly occurring periods of ocular motility and concomitant phenomena during sleep. Science. 1953; 118:361–375
35.
Berger H: Über das Elektrenkephalogramm des Menschen. Archiv für Psychiatrie und Nervenkrankheiten. 1929; 87:527–570
36.
Jouvet M: Research on the neural structures and responsible mechanisms in different phases of physiological sleep. Arch Ital Biol. 1962; 100:125–206
37.
Dahlstrom A, Fuxe K: Localization of monoamines in the lower brain stem. Experientia. 1964; 20:398–399
38.
Pompeiano O: The neurophysiological mechanisms of the postrual and motor events during desynchronized sleep. Res Publ Assoc Res Nerv Ment Dis. 1967; 45:351–423
39.
Hobson JA, Pace‐Schott EF, Stickgold R: Dreaming and the brain: toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. Behav Brain Sci. 2000; 23:793–842
40.
Windt J: Dreaming: A Conceptual Framework for Philosophy of Mind and Empirical Research. Cambridge, Massachusetts; London, England: The MIT Press. 2015 https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt17kk7qt
41.
Voss U, Holzmann R, Tuin I, et al: Lucid dreaming: a state of consciousness with features of both waking and non‐lucid dreaming. Sleep. 2009; 32:1191–1200
42.
Dresler M, Wehrle R, Spoormaker VI, et al: Neural correlates of dream lucidity obtained from contrasting lucid versus non‐lucid REM sleep: a combined EEG/fMRI case study. Sleep. 2012; 35:1017–1020
43.
Cavanna AE, Trimble MR: The precuneus: a review of its functional anatomy and behavioural correlates. Brain. 2006; 129:564–583
44.
Filevich E, Dresler M, Brick TR, et al: Metacognitive mechanisms underlying lucid dreaming. J Neurosci. 2015; 35:1082–1088
45.
Baird B, Castelnovo A, Gosseries O, et al: Frequent lucid dreaming associated with increased functional connectivity between frontopolar cortex and temporoparietal association areas. Sci Rep. 2018; 8:17798
46.
Baird B, Riedner BA, Boly M, et al: Increased lucid dream frequency in long‐term meditators but not following MBSR training. Psychol Cons. 2019;6:40–54
47.
Massimini M, Ferrarelli F, Huber R, et al: Breakdown of cortical effective connectivity during sleep. Science. 2005; 309:2228–2232
48.
Huber R, Ghilardi MF, Massimini M, et al: Local sleep and learning. Nature. 2004; 430:78–81
49.
Nir Y, Staba RJ, Andrillon T, et al: Regional slow waves and spindles in human sleep. Neuron. 2011; 70:153–169
50.
Andrillon T, Nir Y, Staba RJ, et al: Sleep spindles in humans: insights from intracranial EEG and unit recordings. J Neurosci. 2011; 31:17821–17834
51.
Zeki S: The Ferrier Lecture 1995 behind the seen: the functional specialization of the brain in space and time. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2005; 360:1145–1183
52.
Zeki S, Shipp S: The functional logic of cortical connections. Nature. 1988; 335:311–317
53.
Gregory RL: Perceptions as hypotheses. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B. 1980; 290:181–197
54.
Hong CC, Harris JC, Pearlson GD, et al: fMRI evidence for multisensory recruitment associated with rapid eye movements during sleep. Hum Brain Mapp. 2008; 30:1705–1722
55.
Hong CC, Fallon JH, Friston KJ, et al: Rapid eye movements in sleep furnish a unique probe into consciousness. Front Psychol. 2018; 9:2087
56.
Gott JA, Liley DT, Hobson JA: Towards a functional understanding of PGO waves. Front Hum Neurosci. 2017; 11:89
57.
Lim AS, Lozano AM, Moro E, et al: Characterization of REM‐sleep associated ponto‐geniculo‐occipital waves in the human pons. Sleep. 2007; 30:823–827
58.
Stahl SM: Basic psychopharmacology of antidepressants, part 1: antidepressants have seven distinct mechanisms of action. J Clin Psychiatr. 1998; 59:5–14
59.
Hobson A: Psychodynamic Neurology Dreams, Consciousness, and Virtual Reality. Hoboken, NJ, CRC Press, 2015
60.
Riemann D, Krone LB, Wulff K, et al: Sleep, insomnia, and depression. Neuropsychopharmacology. 2020; 45:74–89
61.
Biard K, Douglass AB, De Koninck J: The effects of galantamine and buspirone on sleep structure: implications for understanding sleep abnormalities in major depression. J Psychopharmacol. 2015; 29:1106–1111
62.
Hobson JA, Hong CC, Friston KJ: Virtual reality and consciousness inference in dreaming. Front Psychol. 2014; 5:1133
63.
Knill DC, Pouget A: The Bayesian brain: the role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends Neurosci. 2004; 27:712–719
64.
Powers AR, Mathys C, Corlett PR: Pavlovian conditioning–induced hallucinations result from overweighting of perceptual priors. Science. 2017; 357:596–600
65.
Edwards MJ, Adams RA, Brown H, et al: A Bayesian account of 'hysteria'. Brain. 2012; 135:3495–3512. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/aws129
66.
Catani M, Ffytche DH: The rises and falls of disconnection syndromes. Brain. 2005; 128:2224–2239
67.
Dresler M, Wehrle R, Spoormaker VI, et al: Neural correlates of insight in dreaming and psychosis. Sleep Med Rev. 2015; 20:92–99
68.
Metzinger T: The myth of cognitive agency: subpersonal thinking as a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy. Front Psychol. 2013; 4:931. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00931
69.
Clark A: Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci. 2013; 36:181–204
70.
Seth AK: Inference to the best prediction; in Open MIND. Edited by Metzinger TK, Windt JM. Frankfurt am Main, MIND Group, 2015
71.
Hohwy J: The Predictive Mind. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 2013
72.
Friston KJ, Daunizeau J, Kilner J, et al: Action and behavior: a free‐energy formulation. Biol Cybern. 2010; 102:227–260
73.
Borji A, Itti L: State‐of‐the‐Art in visual attention modeling. IEEE Trans Pattern Anal Mach Intell. 2013; 35:185–207
74.
Friston KJ, Frith CD: Schizophrenia: a disconnection syndrome? Clin Neurosci. 1995; 3:89–97
75.
Parr T, Rees G, Friston KJ: Computational neuropsychology and Bayesian inference. Front Hum Neurosci. 2018; 12:61
76.
Parr T, Benrimoh D, Vincent P, et al: Precision and false perceptual inference. Front Integr Neurosci. 2018. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnint.2018.00039
77.
Moran RJ, Campo P, Symmonds M, et al: Free energy, precision and learning: the role of cholinergic neuromodulation. J Neurosci. 2013; 33:8227–8236
78.
Clark A: The many faces of precision. Front Psychol. 2013; 4:270
79.
Parr T, Friston KJ: Uncertainty, epistemics and active inference. J R Soc Interface. 2017; 14:20170376
80.
Kirchhoff M, Parr T, Palacios E, et al: The Markov blankets of life: autonomy, active inference and the free energy principle. J R Soc Interface. 2018; 15. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2017.0792
81.
Clark A: How to knit your own Markov blanket; in Philosophy and Predictive Processing. Edited by Metzinger TK, Wiese W. Frankfurt am Main, MIND Group, 2017
82.
Friston K: Life as we know it. J R Soc Interface. 2013; 10:20130475
83.
Crooks GE: Measuring thermodynamic length. Phys Rev Lett. 2007; 99:100602
84.
Revonsuo A. Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon. London, UK; Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 2009
85.
Hobson JA: 13 Dreams Freud Never Had: The New Mind Science. New York, NY, Pi, 2005
86.
Stumbrys T, Erlacher D, Johnson M, et al: The phenomenology of lucid dreaming: an online survey. Am J Psychol. 2014; 127:191–204
87.
Sengupta B, Tozzi A, Cooray GK, et al: Towards a neuronal gauge theory. PLoS Biol. 2016; 14: e1002400
88.
Kim E‐J: Investigating information geometry in classical and quantum systems through information length. Entropy. 2018; 20:574
89.
Bob P, Mashour GA: Schizophrenia, dissociation, and consciousness. Conscious Cognit. 2011; 20:1042–1049
90.
Preller KH, Razi A, Zeidman P, et al: Effective connectivity changes in LSD‐induced altered states of consciousness in humans. Proc Natl Acad Sci Unit States Am. 2019; 116:2743–2748
91.
Van de Cruys S, Evers K, Van der Hallen R, et al: Precise minds in uncertain worlds: predictive coding in autism. Psychol Rev. 2014; 121:649–675
92.
Happe F, Frith U: The weak coherence account: detail‐focused cognitive style in autism spectrum disorders. J Autism Dev Disord. 2006; 36:5–25
93.
Srinivasan MV, Laughlin SB, Dubs A: Predictive coding: a fresh view of inhibition in the retina. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1982; 216:427–459
94.
Rao RP, Ballard DH: Predictive coding in the visual cortex: a functional interpretation of some extra‐classical receptive‐field effects. Nat Neurosci. 1999; 2:79–87
95.
Vuust P, Dietz MJ, Witek M, et al: Now you hear it: a predictive coding model for understanding rhythmic incongruity. Ann N Y Acad Sci. 2018. https://doi.org/10.1111/nyas.13622. Epub ahead of print. 29683495
96.
Shipp S: Neural elements for predictive coding. Front Psychol. 2016; 7:1792
97.
Seth AK, Friston KJ: Active interoceptive inference and the emotional brain. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2016; 371. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0007
98.
Ainley V, Apps MA, Fotopoulou A, et al: Bodily precision': A predictive coding account of individual differences in interoceptive accuracy. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2016; 371
99.
Kanai R, Komura Y, Shipp S, et al: Cerebral hierarchies: predictive processing, precision and the pulvinar. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2015; 370
100.
Loeliger H‐A: Least squares and Kalman filtering on Forney graphs; in Codes, Graphs, and Systems: A Celebration of the Life and Career of G David Forney, Jr on the Occasion of his Sixtieth Birthday. Edited by Blahut RE, Koetter R. Boston, MA, Springer US, 2002. pp. 113–135
101.
Feldman H, Friston KJ: Attention, uncertainty, and free‐energy. Front Hum Neurosci. 2010; 4:215
102.
Abbott LF, Varela J, Sen K, et al: Synaptic depression and cortical gain control. Science. 1997; 275:220–224
103.
Lisman J: Excitation, inhibition, local oscillations, or large‐scale loops: what causes the symptoms of schizophrenia? Curr Opin Neurobiol. 2012; 22:537–544
104.
Kann O, Papageorgiou IE, Draguhn A: Highly energized inhibitory interneurons are a central element for information processing in cortical networks. J Cerebr Blood Flow Metabol. 2014; 34:1270–1282
105.
Cruikshank SJ, Ahmed OJ, Stevens TR, et al: Thalamic control of layer 1 circuits in prefrontal cortex. J Neurosci. 2012; 32:17813–17823
106.
Sohal VS, Zhang F, Yizhar O, et al: Parvalbumin neurons and gamma rhythms enhance cortical circuit performance. Nature. 2009; 459:698–702
107.
Breakspear M, Heitmann S, Daffertshofer A: Generative models of cortical oscillations: neurobiological implications of the Kuramoto model. Front Hum Neurosci. 2010; 4:190. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2010.00190.
108.
Fries P: A mechanism for cognitive dynamics: neuronal communication through neuronal coherence. Trends Cogn Sci. 2005; 9:476–480
109.
Dayan P: Twenty‐five lessons from computational neuromodulation. Neuron. 2012; 76:240–256
110.
Krystal JH, Karper LP, Seibyl JP, et al: Subanesthetic effects of the noncompetitive NMDA antagonist, ketamine, in humans. Psychotomimetic, perceptual, cognitive, and neuroendocrine responses. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1994; 51:199–214
111.
Parr T, Friston KJ: Attention or salience? Curr Opin Psychol. 2019; 29:1–5
112.
Auksztulewicz R, Friston K: Attentional enhancement of auditory mismatch responses: a DCM/MEG study. Cereb Cortex. 2015; 25:4273–4283
113.
Kok P, Jehee JF, de Lange FP: Less is more: expectation sharpens representations in the primary visual cortex. Neuron. 2012; 75:265–270
114.
Chatzisarantis NLD, Hagger MS: Mindfulness and the intention‐behavior relationship within the theory of planned behavior. Pers Soc Psychol Bull. 2007; 33:663–676
115.
Limanowski J, Blankenburg F: Minimal self‐models and the free energy principle. Front Hum Neurosci. 2013; 7:547
116.
Metzinger T. Being no one; in The Self‐Model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 2003
117.
Limanowski J, Friston K: ‘Seeing the dark’: grounding phenomenal transparency and opacity in precision estimation for active inference. Front Psychol. 2018; 9:643
118.
Seth AK: Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends Cogn Sci. 2013; 17:565–573
119.
Smith R, Lane RD, Parr T, et al: Neurocomputational mechanisms underlying emotional awareness: insights afforded by deep active inference and their potential clinical relevance. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2019; 107:473–491
120.
Rae CL, Critchley HD, Seth AK: A Bayesian account of the sensory‐motor interactions underlying symptoms of Tourette syndrome. Front Psychiatr. 2019; 10:29. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyt.2019.00029
121.
Friston KJ: Precision psychiatry. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimag. 2017; 2:640–643
122.
Krahe C, Springer A, Weinman JA, et al: The social modulation of pain: others as predictive signals of salience—a systematic review. Front Hum Neurosci. 2013; 7:386
123.
Gu X, Eilam‐Stock T, Zhou T, et al: Autonomic and brain responses associated with empathy deficits in autism spectrum disorder. Hum Brain Mapp. 2015; 36:3323–3338
124.
Paton B, Hohwy J, Enticott PG: The rubber hand illusion reveals proprioceptive and sensorimotor differences in autism spectrum disorders. J Autism Dev Disord. 2012; 42:1870–1883
125.
Adams RA, Aponte E, Marshall L, et al: Active inference and oculomotor pursuit: the dynamic causal modelling of eye movements. J Neurosci Methods. 2015; 242:1–14
126.
Bhatt MB, Bowen S, Rossiter HE, et al: Computational modelling of movement‐related beta‐oscillatory dynamics in human motor cortex. Neuroimage. 2016; 133:224–232
127.
Cornwell BR, Garrido MI, Overstreet C, et al: The unpredictive brain under threat: a neurocomputational account of anxious hypervigilance. Biol Psychiatry. 2017; 82:447–454
128.
Clark JE, Watson S, Friston KJ: What is mood? A computational perspective. Psychol Med. 2018; 48:2277–2284
129.
Stephan KE, Manjaly ZM, Mathys CD, et al: Allostatic self‐efficacy: a metacognitive theory of dyshomeostasis‐induced fatigue and depression. Front Hum Neurosci. 2016; 10:550
130.
Peters A, McEwen BS, Friston K: Uncertainty and stress: why it causes diseases and how it is mastered by the brain. Prog Neurobiol. 2017; 156:164–188. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pneurobio.2017.05.004
131.
Stephan KE, Friston KJ, Frith CD: Dysconnection in schizophrenia: from abnormal synaptic plasticity to failures of self‐monitoring. Schizophr Bull. 2009; 35:509–527
132.
Pellicano E, Burr D: When the world becomes 'too real': a Bayesian explanation of autistic perception. Trends Cogn Sci. 2012; 16:504–510
133.
Lawson RP, Mathys C, Rees G: Adults with autism overestimate the volatility of the sensory environment. Nat Neurosci. 2017; 20:1293–1299
134.
Palmer CJ, Lawson RP, Hohwy J: Bayesian approaches to autism: towards volatility, action, and behavior. Psychol Bull. 2017;143:521–542
135.
Benrimoh D, Parr T, Adams RA, et al: Hallucinations both in and out of context: an active inference account. PLoS One. 2019; 14:e0212379
136.
Powers AR, 3rd, Gancsos MG, Finn ES, et al: Ketamine‐Induced hallucinations. Psychopathology. 2015; 48:376–385
137.
Notredame CE, Pins D, Deneve S, et al: What visual illusions teach us about schizophrenia. Front Integr Neurosci. 2014; 8:63
138.
Adams RA, Stephan KE, Brown HR, et al: The computational anatomy of psychosis. Front Psychiatry. 2013; 4:47
139.
Corlett PR, Honey GD, Krystal JH, et al: Glutamatergic model psychoses: prediction error, learning, and inference. Neuropsychopharmacology. 2011; 36:294–315
140.
Fletcher PC, Frith CD: Perceiving is believing: a Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2009; 10:48–58
141.
Wiese W: Action is enabled by systematic misrepresentations. Erkenntnis. 2017; 82:1233–1252
142.
Oestreich LK, Mifsud NG, Ford JM, et al: Subnormal sensory attenuation to self‐generated speech in schizotypy: electrophysiological evidence for a 'continuum of psychosis. Int J Psychophysiol. 2015; 97:131–138
143.
Parees I, Brown H, Nuruki A, et al: Loss of sensory attenuation in patients with functional (psychogenic) movement disorders. Brain. 2014; 137:2916–2921
144.
Brown H, Adams RA, Parees I, et al: Active inference, sensory attenuation and illusions. Cognit Process. 2013; 14:411–427
145.
Joyce DW, Averbeck BB, Frith CD, et al: Examining belief and confidence in schizophrenia. Psychol Med. 2013; 43:2327–2338
146.
Averbeck BB, Evans S, Chouhan V, et al: Probabilistic learning and inference in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2011; 127:115–122
147.
Shergill SS, Samson G, Bays PM, et al: Evidence for sensory prediction deficits in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry. 2005; 162:2384–2386
148.
Butler PD, Silverstein SM, Dakin SC: Visual perception and its impairment in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry. 2008; 64:40–47
149.
Fogelson N, Litvak V, Peled A, et al: The functional anatomy of schizophrenia: a dynamic causal modeling study of predictive coding. Schizophr Res. 2014; 158:204–212
150.
Jardri R, Hugdahl K, Hughes M, et al: Are hallucinations due to an imbalance between excitatory and inhibitory influences on the brain? Schizophr Bull. 2016; 42:1124–1134
151.
Ranlund S, Adams RA, Diez A, et al: Impaired prefrontal synaptic gain in people with psychosis and their relatives during the mismatch negativity. Hum Brain Mapp. 2016; 37:351–365
152.
Timms AE, Dorschner MO, Wechsler J, et al: Support for the N‐methyl‐D‐aspartate receptor hypofunction hypothesis of schizophrenia from exome sequencing in multiplex families. JAMA Psychiatry. 2013; 70:582–590
153.
Gonzalez‐Burgos G, Lewis DA: NMDA receptor hypofunction, parvalbumin‐positive neurons, and cortical gamma oscillations in schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2012; 38:950–957
154.
Olney JW, Newcomer JW, Farber NB: NMDA receptor hypofunction model of schizophrenia. J Psychiatr Res. 1999; 33:523–533
155.
Stephan KE, Baldeweg T, Friston KJ: Synaptic plasticity and dysconnection in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry. 2006; 59:929–939
156.
Uhlhaas PJ, Singer W: Abnormal neural oscillations and synchrony in schizophrenia. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2010; 11:100–113
157.
Lisman JE, Coyle JT, Green RW, et al: Circuit‐based framework for understanding neurotransmitter and risk gene interactions in schizophrenia. Trends Neurosci. 2008; 31:234–242
158.
Sterzer P, Adams RA, Fletcher P, et al: The predictive coding account of psychosis. Biol Psychiatr. 2018; 84:634–643
159.
Fenelon G, Mahieux F, Huon R, et al: Hallucinations in Parkinson's disease ‐ prevalence, phenomenology and risk factors. Brain. 2000; 123:733–745
160.
Young MP, Hilgetag C, Scannell JW: Models of paradoxical lesion effects and rules of inference for imputing function to structure in the brain. Neurocomputing. 1999; 26‐27:933–938
161.
Sprague JM: Interaction of cortex and superior colliculus in mediation of visually guided behavior in the cat. Science. 1966; 153:1544–1547
162.
Kapur N, Pascual‐Leone A, Della Sala S, et al: The Paradoxical Brain. Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press, 2015
163.
Keshavan MS, Sudarshan M: Deep dreaming, aberrant salience and psychosis: connecting the dots by artificial neural networks. Schizophr Res. 2017; 188:178–181
164.
Kapur S: Psychosis as a state of aberrant salience: a framework linking biology, phenomenology, and pharmacology in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry. 2003; 160:13–23
165.
Nour MM, Carhart‐Harris RL: Psychedelics and the science of self‐experience. Br J Psychiatry: J Ment Sci. 2017; 210:177–179
166.
Cuijpers P, Sijbrandij M, Koole SL, et al: The efficacy of psychotherapy and pharmacotherapy in treating depressive and anxiety disorders: a meta‐analysis of direct comparisons. World Psychiatr. 2013; 12:137–148
167.
Chekroud AM, Krystal JH: Personalised pharmacotherapy: an interim solution for antidepressant treatment? BMJ. 2015; 350:h2502
168.
Chekroud AM: Unifying treatments for depression: an application of the free energy principle. Front Psychol. 2015; 6:153
169.
Beedie SA, Benson PJ, St Clair DM: Atypical scanpaths in schizophrenia: evidence of a trait‐ or state‐dependent phenomenon? J Psychiatry Neurosci. 2011; 36:150–164
170.
Russo M, Carrarini C, Dono F, et al. The pharmacology of visual hallucinations in synucleinopathies. Front Pharmacol. 2019; 10:1379
171.
Owens AP, Allen M, Ondobaka S, et al: Interoceptive inference: from computational neuroscience to clinic. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2018; 90:174–183. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2018.04.017
172.
Feldman AG: New insights into action‐perception coupling. Exp Brain Res. 2009; 194:39–58
173.
Mansell W: Control of perception should be operationalized as a fundamental property of the nervous system. Top Cogn Sci. 2011; 3:257–261
174.
Mohan V, Morasso P: Passive motion paradigm: an alternative to optimal control. Front Neurorobot. 2011; 5:4
175.
Friston K, Schwartenbeck P, FitzGerald T, et al: The anatomy of choice: dopamine and decision‐making. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2014; 369
176.
Palmer CE, Auksztulewicz R, Ondobaka S, et al: Sensorimotor beta power reflects the precision‐weighting afforded to sensory prediction errors. Neuroimage. 2019; 200:59–71
177.
Letzkus JJ, Wolff SB, Luthi A: Disinhibition, a circuit mechanism for associative learning and memory. Neuron. 2015; 88:264–276
178.
Douglas RJ, Martin KA: A functional microcircuit for cat visual cortex. J Physiol. 1991; 440:735–769
179.
Freeman WJ: Simulation of chaotic EEG patterns with a dynamic model of the olfactory system. Biol Cybern. 1987; 56:139–150
180.
Snead OC, 3rd: Basic mechanisms of generalized absence seizures. Ann Neurol. 1995; 37:146–157
181.
Omidvarnia A, Pedersen M, Rosch RE, et al: Hierarchical disruption in the Bayesian brain: focal epilepsy and brain networks. NeuroImage Clinical. 2017; 15:682–688
182.
Elazar Z, Hobson JA: Neuronal excitability control in health and disease: a neurophysiological comparison of REM sleep and epilepsy. Prog Neurobiol. 1985; 25:141–188
183.
Freud S: Dostoevsky and parricide. Int J Psycho‐Analysis. 1945; 26:1–8
184.
Hasler G, Drevets WC, Manji HK, et al: Discovering endophenotypes for major depression. Neuropsychopharmacology. 2004; 29:1765–1781
185.
Ferrarelli F, Peterson MJ, Sarasso S, et al: Thalamic dysfunction in schizophrenia suggested by whole‐night deficits in slow and fast spindles. Am J Psychiatr. 2010; 167:1339–1348
186.
Cheeta S, Ruigt G, vanProosdij J, et al: Changes in sleep architecture following chronic mild stress. Biol Psychiatr. 1997; 41:419–427
187.
Kuula L, Merikanto I, Makkonen T, et al: Schizotypal traits are associated with sleep spindles and rapid eye movement in adolescence. J Sleep Res. 2018; 28:e12692. https://doi.org/10.1111/jsr.12692
188.
Baglioni C, Nanovska S, Regen W, et al: Sleep and mental disorders: a meta‐analysis of polysomnographic research. Psychol Bull. 2016; 142:969–990
189.
Ferrarelli F, Tononi G: The thalamic reticular nucleus and schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2011; 37:306–315
190.
Manoach DS, Pan JQ, Purcell SM, et al: Reduced sleep spindles in schizophrenia: a treatable endophenotype that links risk genes to impaired cognition? Biol Psychiatr. 2016; 80:599–608
191.
Manoach DS, Stickgold R: Does abnormal sleep impair memory consolidation in schizophrenia? Front Hum Neurosci. 2009; 3:21. https://doi.org/10.3389/neuro.09.021.2009
192.
Orem J, Lydic R: Upper airway function during sleep and wakefulness: experimental studies on normal and anesthetized cats. 1978 [classical article]. Sleep. 2002; 25:49–68
193.
Orem J, Lydic R: Upper airway function during sleep and wakefulness: experimental studies on normal and anesthetized cats. Sleep. 1978; 1:49–68
194.
Guilleminault C: Clinical Neurophysiology of Sleep Disorders. Edinburgh, UK, Elsevier, 2006
195.
Hobson JA: Sleep mechanisms and pathophysiology: some clinical implications of the reciprocal Interaction hypothesis of sleep cycle control. Psychosom Med. 1983; 45:123–140
196.
Horne S, Hay K, Watson S, et al: An evaluation of sleep disturbance on in‐patient psychiatric units in the UK. BJPsych Bull. 2018; 42:193–197

Information & Authors

Information

Published In

Go to Psychiatric Research and Clinical Practice
Psychiatric Research and Clinical Practice
Pages: 12 - 28

History

Received: 12 July 2020
Accepted: 14 October 2020
Published online: 10 November 2020
Published in print: Spring 2021

Authors

Details

J. Allan Hobson, M.D.
Division of Sleep Medicine, Harvard Medical School, Boston, Massachusetts (J. A. Hobson); Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University, Nijmegen (J. A. Gott); The Wellcome Centre for Human Neuroimaging, University College London, London (K. J. Friston)
Jarrod A. Gott, Ph.D.
Division of Sleep Medicine, Harvard Medical School, Boston, Massachusetts (J. A. Hobson); Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University, Nijmegen (J. A. Gott); The Wellcome Centre for Human Neuroimaging, University College London, London (K. J. Friston)
Karl J. Friston, FRS
Division of Sleep Medicine, Harvard Medical School, Boston, Massachusetts (J. A. Hobson); Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University, Nijmegen (J. A. Gott); The Wellcome Centre for Human Neuroimaging, University College London, London (K. J. Friston)

Notes

Send correspondence to Prof. Friston ([email protected])

Funding Information

Wellcome Trust: 088130/Z/09/Z

Metrics & Citations

Metrics

Citations

Export Citations

If you have the appropriate software installed, you can download article citation data to the citation manager of your choice. Simply select your manager software from the list below and click Download.

For more information or tips please see 'Downloading to a citation manager' in the Help menu.

Format
Citation style
Style
Copy to clipboard

View Options

View options

PDF/EPUB

View PDF/EPUB

Get Access

Login options

Already a subscriber? Access your subscription through your login credentials or your institution for full access to this article.

Personal login Institutional Login Open Athens login

Not a subscriber?

Subscribe Now / Learn More

PsychiatryOnline subscription options offer access to the DSM-5-TR® library, books, journals, CME, and patient resources. This all-in-one virtual library provides psychiatrists and mental health professionals with key resources for diagnosis, treatment, research, and professional development.

Need more help? PsychiatryOnline Customer Service may be reached by emailing [email protected] or by calling 800-368-5777 (in the U.S.) or 703-907-7322 (outside the U.S.).

Media

Figures

Other

Tables

Share

Share

Share article link

Share